LINGUIST List 12.2582

Tue Oct 16 2001

Review: Butt & Holloway King, Argument Realization

Editor for this issue: Terence Langendoen <terrylinguistlist.org>


What follows is another discussion note contributed to our Book Discussion Forum. We expect these discussions to be informal and interactive; and the author of the book discussed is cordially invited to join in.

If you are interested in leading a book discussion, look for books announced on LINGUIST as "available for discussion." (This means that the publisher has sent us a review copy.) Then contact Simin Karimi at siminlinguistlist.org or Terry Langendoen at terrylinguistlist.org.


Directory

  • Simon Musgrave, Review of Butt & Holloway King, Argument Realization

    Message 1: Review of Butt & Holloway King, Argument Realization

    Date: Tue, 16 Oct 2001 10:27:46 +0200
    From: Simon Musgrave <S.Musgravelet.leidenuniv.nl>
    Subject: Review of Butt & Holloway King, Argument Realization


    Butt, Miriam & Tracy Holloway King, eds. (2000) Argument Realization. CSLI Publications, x+244pp, paperback ISBN 1-57586-266-2, $25.00, hardback ISBN 1-57586-265-4, Studies in Constraint-Based Lexicalism

    Simon Musgrave, Spinoza Project: Lexicon & Syntax University of Leiden Centre for Linguistics

    [An announcement of this book can be found at http://linguistlist.org/issues/12/12-703.html#1 --reviewer]

    This volume is a collection of seven papers dealing in various ways with the issue of how the semantic arguments of predicates are realised in the expressions of language. An introduction by the editors, a subject index and a name index are also included. All the papers are written within the theoretical framework of Lexical-Functional Grammar (LFG)(Bresnan 2001). This theory has three types of structure which are relevant to the issues with which the papers deal. Argument structure (a-structure) models the relations of predicates and arguments independent of any syntactic encoding. Functional structure (f-structure) models the relations of predicates and grammatical functions such as subject and object. And constituent structure (c-structure) models the surface syntactic form of linguistic expressions. Correspondence principles constrain the mapping between structures, but the information encoded in each structure is distinct. The questions addressed in this book are about the nature of these correspondence principles and how they work in particular languages.

    In their introduction, the editors divide the papers into three groups, those dealing with the issue of the division of labour between morphology and syntax, those dealing with complex predicates, and those dealing with linking theory (Carter 1976). In the terms of the sketch of the theoretical framework just given, the first group of papers deal with the correspondence between f-structure and c- structure and the third group deal with the correspondence between a-structure and f-structure. The analysis of complex predicates raises problems for both sets of correspondence principles: in the first case, the issue of the shared properties of morphological and periphrastic complex predications, and in the second case , the issue of how complex events can be coded as one set of predicate- argument relations. This grouping is logical, but one important interrelation is not discussed by the editors. The papers by Sadler and Laczk� both deal with the status of semantic arguments within NP, and both analyses crucially depend on the possessor function.

    B�rjars and Vincent (Multiple Case and the 'Wimpishness' of Morphology - B&V) argue that properties of the morphological system of a language can constrain the realisation of syntactic features. The crucial data come from situations in which a certain NP or element of an NP can be analysed as having two case features assigned to it. In some languages, both features can be expressed (case- stacking or Suffixaufnahme), and in other languages only one feature is expressed, but this may not be the expected one (what B&V call over-riding). B&V point out the typologically interesting fact that there are apparently no languages with fusional morphology and case-stacking, and no languages with agglutinative morphology and over-riding. Therefore, the surface expression of similar feature structures in different languages is constrained only by properties internal to the morphological component of the language.

    Nordlinger (Australian Case Systems: Towards a Constructive Solution - N) also deals with case-stacking in her paper, which is in effect an introductory presentation of the material covered in detail in Nordlinger (1998). N's analysis reverses the usual assumption as to how case- marking works. Rather than the case morphology being the reflex of a syntactic feature assigned to a dependent, the case marker is treated as a feature of the dependent which constructs the wider environment in which it occurs. Thus, in a simple case, a NP with accusative case carries the information that it will be the value of the attribute OBJ in some larger f-structure (assuming NOM-ACC alignment). This is handled formally by inside-out function assignment (Halvorsen & Kaplan 1988). A Principle of Morphological Composition allows this process to extend to the case- stacking examples. This principle guarantees that the information contributed by a morpheme will be unified with the outermost f-structure constructed by the stem to which it attaches. The effect of the principle is vacuous except in those cases where inside-out function assignment is specified.

    Sadler's paper (Noun Phrase Structure in Welsh - S) addresses the problem of word order in Welsh NPs. The head is usually initial in such phrases, but a possessor appears closer to the head than apparent PP complements. This order has been accounted for by analysing the position of the head as the result of movement from within NP to some dominating functional projection. S argues in detail against one version of this analysis, that of Rouveret (1994), although the general line of argumentation could be used against other similar proposals. The alternative analysis for which S argues is that Welsh nominals, and probably nominals in all Gaelic languages, do not project any argument structure except a possessor slot. This is not to say that deverbal nouns may not have semantic arguments, but syntactically they must always be realised as possessors, or as adjuncts which are adjoined to NP. This analysis accounts for the fact that possessors and adjectives appear between the head and its apparent PP complements, and also for some co-ordination facts which are not easily handled in the head-raising analysis.

    Broadwell's paper (Choctaw Directionals and the Syntax of Complex Predication - B) is an analysis of directional particles in the American language Choctaw. A similar function, that of specifying the direction of motion, is served by verbal morphology in some other languages, such as Oneida. B analyses both types as complex predications, the difference between the two being parallel to that between morphological and periphrastic causatives. The directional particles normally immediately precede the verb, but B offers convincing arguments that they are separate words and that they are not members of the rather limited class of adverbs in Choctaw. The remainder of B's paper is devoted to discussing the semantic condition which governs the use of directional particles. B argues that if the conceptual representation of a verb includes the element GO, then a directional particle is compatible with it but not otherwise. This claim has the interesting consequence that some verbs which are not obviously motion verbs must nevertheless, at least for Choctaw, have the motion component GO included in their conceptual representation.

    Matsumoto (Crosslinguistic Parameterization of Causative Predicates - M), using data from Japanese, argues that the typology of causatives is more complex than is assumed by, for example, Alsina (1997 and elsewhere). M presents data which suggests that the distinction between two types of causative which is crucial to Alsina's proposal is a semantic one and that the arguments which are shared can be fused in various ways. This allows for the possibility of causatives which are monoclausal at both a-structure and at f-structure and M argues that this possibility occurs in Japanese. Given this evidence, M proposes that a typology of causatives must take two factors into account: the semantic distinction noted by Alsina, and the complexity of the structures involved. Of the six logical possibilities, M notes that two are not represented in the languages he has examined, and he argues that these gaps are principled and not accidental.

    L�drup (Underspecification in Lexical Mapping Theory -L) examines intransitive verbs in Norwegian and presents evidence that the distinction between unergative and unaccusative verbs breaks down in some environments. Existential sentences are predicted only to be possible with unaccusative verbs, but Norwegian allows unergative verbs in this clause type. On the other hand, it is well known that unaccusatives can appear freely with resultatives while unergatives require a fake reflexive (Simpson 1983, Levin and Rapaport-Hovav 1995), but in Norwegian, unaccusatives also can have fake reflexives in resultative clauses. L argues that these data can be handled in LFG by underspecification of features in Lexical Mapping Theory (LMT), the LFG version of linking theory. L suggests that the basic intuition to be captured is that agents and themes do not have their prototypical properties in the absence of the other role.

    Lazck�'s paper (Derived Nominals, Possessors, and Lexical Mapping Theory - La) is a discussion of the properties of deverbal nominals in Hungarian, focussing on their argument-taking properties and the status of the possessor constituent. He demonstrates that the Hungarian NP has only one argument position available, the possessor slot, and that this position is filled for event nominalisations on an ergative basis. That is, the subject of an intransitive verb will become possessor in the nominalisation, but the object of a transitive verb will fill this slot. The subject of a transitive verb can only be realised in a postpositional phrase. Mapping to the clausal function subject is reserved for the most thematically prominent argument (in the normal case), but in Hungarian NPs, the less thematically prominent argument maps to possessor. La proposes a reversal of the association principles which LMT applies for clausal argruments, a stipulative solution. However, in a footnote, he offers a more convincing account. The patient-like argument cannot be realised as an oblique due to a feature clash, while the agent-like argument can. Therefore, it is only necessary to assume some principle such as full interpretation to account for the observed pattern. The final section of La's paper discusses various properties of the possessive morpheme in Hungarian.

    The majority of these papers were originally presented at conferences organised by the LFG community, and the first observation to make in evaluating the volume is that it reflects an eclectic and active research community. At the level of presentation, the editing is generally good. A few misprints remain, the section numbering in Nordlinger's paper goes awry, and Laczk�'s prose is occasionally obscure, but the text is readable. However, at the level of content I am did feel at times that the editors might have been more demanding, and I will discuss two examples of this briefly.

    Broadwell's paper offers very little argumentation that the phenomena being discussed are examples of complex predication. Having shown that in some languages the relevant meanings are expressed morphologically, and in some other languages they are expressed syntactically, Broadwell then assumes that complex predication is involved. No details are given of how the argument-taking properties of the verbs change when they combine with directional particles, nor data as to whether the directional meaning falls within the scope of negation or of tense and aspect. The data presented gave me the impression that an analysis that treated directional particles as a type of verbal modifier would be just as valid as the analysis which appeals to complex predication. The bulk of the paper, which deals with the semantic conditions constraining the use of directionals would be unchanged under the alternative analysis, and would retain its interest.

    In L�drup's paper, part of the argument relating to resultatives depends on the claim that clauses with fake reflexives must have the same structure whether the verb is unaccusative or unergative. The unergative verb possibility is, not surprisingly, taken to be unmarked, the subject of such a verb is assigned the intrinsic feature [-o(bjective)] by LMT. Therefore, L�drup argues that in a clause with an unaccusative verb the subject must also have the intrinsic feature [-o], against the assumptions of LMT. But this argument occurs in the paper after it has already been argued that the subject of unergative verbs can have the intrinsic feature [-r(estricted)] rather than [-o]; this assumption is needed to account for the existential sentence data. This leaves unclear the status of the argument just sketched: if unergative verbs can have a [-r] subject in existential sentences, need it be assumed that they always have a [-o] subject elsewhere? Additionally, all L�drup's arguments go to show that the distinction between unergatives and unaccusatives is not relevant in the grammar of Norwegian. Nevertheless, the paper is written as though the distinction is valid. It would have been useful if evidence had been presented showing where the distinction has consequences which are not undermined by L�drup's account. As it stands, the paper gives the impression that the terms 'unergative' and 'unaccusative' are used only to refer to the semantic character of the various verbs. This point is of more general theoretical interest within LFG. The capacity of LMT to provide a natural account of unaccusativity and resultatives is taken as evidence in favour of the approach in e.g. Bresnan 2001. As presented, the Norwegian data weaken this argument, but if it is the case that the unergative/unaccusative distinction is not relevant in Norwegian syntax, then the more general argument is not affected.

    These reservations should not discourage readers who are not LFG devotees from sampling this volume. The papers by B�rjars & Vincent and by Matsumoto present findings which will be of interest to many and which are not theory- dependent. Nordlinger's paper is theory-dependent, but it also introduces a fully worked-out proposal for dealing with a complex syntactic phenomenon. The insights presented in the remaining papers are embedded in the theoretical framework to varying degrees, but all discuss data which raise problems for any account of argument realization.

    References:

    Alsina, Alex (1997) A theory of complex predicates: Evidence from causatives in Bantu and Romance. In Alex Alsina, Joan Bresnan & Peter Sells (eds) Complex Predicates, 203-246. Stanford CA: CSLI Publications

    Bresnan, Joan W. (2001) Lexical-Functional Syntax. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers

    Carter, Richard (1976) Some linking regularities. In Beth Levin & Carol Tenny (eds) On Linking: Papers by Richard Carter. Cambridge MA: Center for Cognitive Science MIT (Lexicon Project Working Papers no.25)

    Halvorsen, Per-Kristian and Ronald M. Kaplan. 1988. Projections and semantic description in Lexical-Functional Grammar. In Proceedings of the International Conference on Fifth Generation Computer Systems (FGCS-88), 1116-1122, Tokyo, Japan. Reprinted in Mary Dalrymple, Ronald M. Kaplan, John Maxwell, and Annie Zaenen, eds., Formal Issues in Lexical- Functional Grammar, 279-292. Stanford: CSLI, 1995

    Levin, Beth & Malka Rappaport Hovav (1995) Unaccusativity: At the Syntax-Lexical Semantics Interface. Cambridge MA: MIT Press

    Matsumoto, Yo (1996) Complex Predicates in Japanese: A Syntactic and Semantic Study of the Notion "Word". Stanford: CSLI Publications

    Nordlinger, Rachel (1988) Constructive Case: Evidence from Australian Languages. Stanford: CSLI Publications

    Ramchand, Gillian (1997) Aspect and Predication. Oxford: Oxford University Press

    Rouveret, Alain (1994) Le syntaxe du gallois. Paris: Editions CNRS

    Simpson, Jane (1983) Resultatives. In Lori Levin, Malka Rappaport & Annie Zaenen (eds) Papers in Lexical-Functional Grammar, 143-157. Bloomington IN: Indiana University Linguistic Club

    Simon Musgrave is a post-doctoral researcher at the University of Leiden. His doctoral thesis is a study of non-subject arguments in Indonesian, using LFG as the theoretical framework. He is currently working on a cross- linguistic database for the Spinoza Project, Lexicon & Syntax, and is part of the East Indonesia research group within the project.