LINGUIST List 12.974

Sat Apr 7 2001

Review: Martin et al (eds) Step by Step

Editor for this issue: Simin Karimi <siminlinguistlist.org>


What follows is another discussion note contributed to our Book Discussion Forum. We expect these discussions to be informal and interactive; and the author of the book discussed is cordially invited to join in.

If you are interested in leading a book discussion, look for books announced on LINGUIST as "available for discussion." (This means that the publisher has sent us a review copy.) Then contact Simin Karimi at siminlinguistlist.org or Terry Langendoen at terrylinguistlist.org.


Directory

  • ,

    Message 1:

    Date:
    From: <>
    Subject:


    Roger Martin, David Michaels, and Juan Urigereka (eds.), (2000), Step by Step: Essays on Minimalist Syntax in Honor of Howard Lasnik, MIT Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts. 357pp, $42.95.

    Reviewed by Ahmad R. Lotfi, Azad University

    This collection of essays on minimalist syntax covers a number of current issues in linguistic theory including movement, wh-questions, quantifier scope, temporal relations, relativization, and also representational and derivational approaches to language. The book is dedicated to Howard Lasnik for his twenty-fifth anniversary at the University of Connecticut in 1997. Naturally, the reader witnesses his presence in all essays in this collection. Most probably, however, that will be true for ANY other collection of minimalist papers, too! Thank you, Howard, for everything!

    CONTRIBUTORS: Andrew Barss, Zeliko Boskovic, Noam Chomsky, Hamida Demirdache, Hiroto Hoshi, Kyle Johnson, Roger Martin, Keiko Murasugi, Javier Ormazabal, Mamoru Saito, Daiko Takahashi, Juan Uriagereka, Myriam Uribe-Etxebarria, Ewa Willim.

    CONTENTS: Introduction: Some Possible Foundations of the Minimalist Program (Roger Martin and Juan Uriagereka) 1. Minimalism and Asymmetric Wh-Interpretation (Andrew Barss) 2. Sometimes in [Spec, CP], Sometimes in Situ (Zeliko Boskovic) 3. Minimalist Inquiries: The Framework (Noam Chomsky) 4. The Primitives of Temporal Relations (Hamida Demirdache and Myriam Uribe-Etxebarria) 5. How Far Will Quantifiers Go? (Kyle Johnson) 6. Japanese Complex Noun Phrases and the Antisymmetry Theory (Keiko S. Murasugi) 7. A Conspiracy Theory of Case and Agreement (Javier Ormazabal) 8. The Japanese Light Verb Construction and the Minimalist Program (Mamoru Saito and Hiroto Hoshi) 9. Move F and Raising of Lexical and Empty DPs (Daiko Takahashi) 10. On the Grammar of Polish Nominals (Ewa Willim)

    SYNOPSES AND EVALUATIONS:

    Introduction Some Possible Foundations of the Minimalist Program (Roger Martin and Juan Uriagereka)

    Synopsis Martin and Uriagereka elaborate on two minimalist theses: (a) a "weak minimalist thesis", or *methodological minimalism*, which is not controversial in sciences as it is a search for "simple and nonredundant theories of the world (or Occam's razor)" (p.1), and (b) a "strong minimalist thesis", or *ontological minimalism*, which is concerned with the question of the "optimal design" of language faculty (FL) rather than the issue of "best theory" for it. There is nothing new in the Minimalist Program as far as (a) is concerned. The program is innovative in that it heavily relies on the strong minimalist thesis, which has nothing to do with the weaker thesis after all: "[o]ur explanation may be good, mediocre, or terrible, and it would still be true that FL works as well as it does, perhaps optimally as just suggested" (p.2).

    Lasnik and Saito's (1984) account of movement is an example of a theory good enough both in methodological elegance and empirical coverage. Despite that, Chomsky rejects it in favor of a methodologically less elegant theory of movement (which happens to be less adequate in empirical terms, too, as it does not systematically explain the adjunct/argument asymmetries any more) because of his reliance on the strong thesis. For Lasnik and Saito, "Affect Alpha" (instead of "Move Alpha") affords movement, deletion, and insertion. They also allow back-and-forth movements. Chomsky, on the other hand, rejects such a thing, and, as a result, his theory "needs a new set of axioms, usually referred to as 'last resort' "(p.10).

    Critical evaluation Chomsky's (now classic) assertion that the generative linguist should develop a theory of language for an idealized native-speaker in a homogeneous speech community was essentially a *methodologically* minimalist move that could bring about an elegant theory of language divorced from non linguistic factors necessarily influencing one's linguistic performance. Optimal design of FL is apparently conceivable only for such an idealized speaker of language because in the real-time world, economy is always constrained by such factors as the listener's demand for the speaker to remain maximally distinct in what she produces: while the speaker is interested to get rid of the so called "PF extra-baggage" as soon as possible, the listener, on the other hand, prefers the speaker to keep the PF burden on her shoulders. The trade-off between economy and distinctness seems to have no place in the Minimalist account of FL optimality of design. Hence, what Martin and Uriagereka consider as ontological minimalism is conditional upon methodological minimalism, which makes the program run into trouble as it implies that methodology has motivated a priori the design of the very phenomenon it aims to study! Ontological minimalism, in this sense, is the consequence of methodological minimalism, and, as a result, it makes more sense to say it has every thing to do with the weak minimalist thesis.

    Chapter One Minimalism and Asymmetric Wh-Interpretation (Andrew Barss)

    Synopsis Barss examines two positions on wh-questions recurrent in the literature: (1) wh-scope assignment via movement so that all wh-expressions move to A-bar positions before LF to be interpreted as restricted interrogative quantifiers (Chomsky 1981, Higginbotham and May 1981, Huang 1982, and Lasnik and Saito 1992 among others), and (2) wh-scope assignment and interpretation without movement as such expressions are interpreted in situ (Pesetsky 1987, Cinque 1990, Reinhart 1995, and Chomsky 1995 among others). He hypothesizes that both mechanisms are needed in order to afford a minimalist account of LF. Barss considers the data on multipair reading and superiority, crossed binding asymmetry, asymmetry in wh-QNP interpretations, and comparative superlative to support his hybrid theory of wh-interpretation.

    Critical evaluation Barss's account of wh-interpretation seems not to meet the condition of falsifiability on empirical theories. Barss's hybrid theory is always valid (and as a result, insignificant) as any empirical support for either of the positions mentioned earlier will also support his account of wh interpretation while any empirical challenge to any of these two cannot force Barss into a corner. His analyses are not always informative either. He notices that (contrary to Chomsky's (1995) Shortest Movement Condition) both (22) and (23) below are grammatical:

    (22) Which man do you think helped which woman yesterday?

    (23) Which woman do you think which man helped yesterday?

    According to Barss, the paradox "disappears if we permit the occurrence of [+wh] to be optional on those wh-expressions that need raise to [Spec, C] for interpretation. [...] Here, since only one of the interrogative phrases bears the feature [+wh], the violation of the Shortest Movement Condition is only apparent" (p.39). However, he does not explain why in each case the expression that bears [+wh], and not the other, must do so. This is as informative as saying both (22) and (23) are grammatical because we've got some grammatical option here.

    What would happen to Barss's analysis if English allowed (22) but not (23), or vice versa? All one had got to do then was drop "optional" and say one or the other wh-expression MUST bear [+wh]. Apparently, we do not even need the Shortest Movement Condition any more. It will suffice to say which wh-expression bears [+wh] so that it can move to [Spec, C].

    Chapter Two Sometimes in [Spec, CP], Sometimes in Situ (Zeliko Boskovic)

    Synopsis Boskovic examines French as a "mixed language", in contrast with English, Bulgarian, and Japanese, in the sense that it displays both wh-fronting and wh-in-situ patterns in its multiple questions. Although wh-fronting is always possible, the other pattern is rather constrained as it is not allowed in embedded questions. French and Serbo-Croatian (SC) are parallel in that "[w]here French does not have syntactic wh-movement, SC does not exhibit Superiority effects" (p. 57). They differ in that SC wh-phrases must necessarily undergo fronting when they do not move overtly to [Spec, CP] while they remain in situ in French.

    Boskovic's LF C-insertion analysis of such mixed languages assumes that strong features may be inserted at LF provided that they are checked and deleted immediately. The com plementiser itself is inserted at the root of the tree as a legitimate instance of Merge, which cannot take place in embedded positions as it must necessarily expand structure. The strong [+wh] feature, however, is inserted later at LF. It prevents the wh-in-situ pattern as it would either require the covert expansion of the embedded question via Merge or the overt movement of the wh-phrase. The overt movement proves to be obligatory in embedded questions as merge cannot take place under such circumstances. The LF C-insertion analysis is superior to the optionally strong/ weak [+wh] feature analysis since the former assumes that [+wh] feature is always strong in French and SC.

    Critical evaluation Boskovic's LF C-insertion analysis is an interesting solution to both theoretical and empirical problems. The solution is still minimalist in that it allows lexical insertion to take place at LF only under certain conditions: "[I]f an NP such as *John* is inserted in LF, the derivation crashes because LF cannot interpret phonological features of *John*. If, on the other hand, *John* is inserted in PF, PF will not know how to interpret the semantic features of *John*" (p.55). Boskovic then concludes that "[t]he only way to derive a legitimate PF representation and a legitimate LF represen tation is for *John* to be inserted before the level of S-Structure" (p.55). It follows that only PF insertion of semantically superfluous lexical items and LF insertion of phonologically null elements are allowed in the standard minimalist analyses.

    Despite that, it is still possible to conceive of a radically minimalist model (Lotfi, ms.) in which there is only one single interface level where phonetic, formal, and semantic features are all interpreted by the relevant external systems so that compatibility between a feature, say the formal feature Q, and some external system like C-I (and also its incompatibility with A-P), will ensure a legitimate interpretation. In such a "unitarianist" model of language, a derivation crashes iff at least one of its features (no matter whether semantic, formal, or phonetic) is left uninterpreted when the process of interpretation at Semantico-Phonetic Form (SPF) is over: hence no need to worry about the question of LF-PF mapping. The model can explain (among other things) *John*'s problem of insertion (and also the empirical questions raised in this chapter) as well as Boskovic's without necessitating the split of the interface into PF and LF.

    Chapter Three Minimalist Inquiries: The Framework (Noam Chomsky)

    Synopsis Chomsky's Minimalist Inquiries: the Framework--although still exploratory like The Minimalist Program (1995)--is intended to be a major rethinking of MP issues and 'a clearer account and further development of them' (p.89). A set of fresh terms (e.g. EPP-feature and Agree) are introduced in order to explain the complexities of the functioning of language faculty. The chapter develops Chomsky's MP thesis of movement according to which elements move in the fulfillment of certain morphological requirements. Chomsky assumes movement--or "dislocation", the term Chomsky prefers here--to be an (apparent) "imperfection of language" or a "design flaw" which makes the strong minimalist thesis untenable. Chomsky assumes two examples (of such imperfections) to be uninterpretable features of lexical items and the dislocation property.

    The role of the minimalist program for the syntactic theory remains to be the discovery of the mechanisms that force dislocation. Chomsky considers the uninterpretable inflectional features as the devices employed to yield dislocation. In other words, he thinks these two imperfections might reduce to one, the dislocation property while dislocation might itself be required by design specifications. Chomsky recognizes that "[g]iven some apparent property P of language", it is possible that "(a) P is real, and an imperfection", "(b) P is not real, contrary to what had been supposed", and "(c) P is real, but not an imperfection ..." (p. 112). Although the strongest conclusion (c) is less likely than others to be correct, it is the most interesting one, and as a result, a novel question worthy of asking.

    Critical evaluation Apart from terminology, Chomsky's thesis of movement developed here does not seem to be significantly different from the original ideas discussed earlier in his MP. It is rather an attempt to recast MP terminology in new ones without a serious attempt to define them clearly. Chomsky seems to recognize this strategy himself in note 108 (while discussing the featural composition of AGR): "In MP, it (that Agr consisting only of uninterpretable phi-features should be disallowed, Lotfi) could be avoided only by recourse to the (dubious) distinction between deletion and erasure" (p.151). In absence of clearly stated definitions and empirically motivated distinctions, there will always remain a chance for one's use of new terms and distinctions to prove later to be recourse to dubious ones.

    Chomsky seems to dispense with the concept strength altogether saying: "The concept strength, introduced to force violation of Procrastinate, appears to have no place. It remains to determine whether the effects can be fully captured in minimalist terms or remain as true imperfections" (p. 132). Despite that, he immediately introduces a new term--EPP- feature-- which is functionally similar (at least as far as movement is concerned) to strength as formulated in MP, and a new operation--Agree-- in order to explain the mechanisms underlying movement:

    The operation ... Move, combining Merge and Agree(,) ... establishes agreement between alpha and F and merges P(F) (generalized "pied piping") to alphaP, where P(F) is a phrase determined by F ... and alphaP is a projection headed by alpha. P(F) becomes SPEC-alpha. ... All CFCs (core functional categories) may have phi-features (obligatory for T, v). These are uninterpretable, constituting the core of the systems of (structural) Case-assignment and "dislocation" (Move). ... Each CFC also allows an extra SPEC beyond its s-selection: for C, a raised wh-phrase; for T, the surface subject; for v, the phrase raised by Object Shift (OS). For T, the property is the Extended Projection Principle (EPP). By analogy, we can call the corresponding properties of C and v EPP-features, determining positions not forced by the Projection Principle. EPP-features are uninterpretable ... though the configuration they establish has effects for interpretation. (pp. 101-2)

    He then formulates the configuration (22) below for CFCs "with XP the extra SPEC determined by the EPP-features of the attracting head H" (p.109):

    (22) alpha = [XP [ (EA) H YP ]]

    Typical examples of (22) are raising to subject (yielding (23A)), Object Shift (OS, yielding (B), with XP= DO and t its trace), and overt A'-movement (yielding (C), with H = C and XP a wh-phrase ... :

    (23) a. XP - [T YP] b. XP - [SU [ v [V t ]]] c. XP - [C YP]

    The EPP-features of T might be universal. For the phase heads v/C, it varies parametrically among languages and if available is optional. ... [T]he EPP-feature can be satisfied by Merge of an expletive EXPL in (23a), but not in (23b) and (23c)" (p. 109).

    The LI thesis of movement (like his MP thesis) merely states that things move simply because some mysterious EPP-features up there make them move (as strong features did in his MP account of the thesis). And by EPP-features he means those features we understand must be there because of the raising of an element to the new position. Since choice of Move over Agree follows from presence of EPP-features, and since such features are uninterpretable ones presumably doomed to deletion in the course of derivation, we are once more left with the question of why they should be there after all. Chomsky's allusion to "certain semantic properties" involving dislocated structures seems to have something to do with such functionalist theories as parsing or theme-rheme structure in explaining the why of movement. Chomsky has set himself on the exploration of the mechanisms involved in movement. Then one may wonder how the nature could anticipate (if it did) our future need to such (then useless) uninterpretable features as that part of the computational mechanism we will happen to employ later when we want to move things for meaning's sake. One possibility is that such features evolved later to take care of our already existing needs to communicate meaning. The other possibility, which is more in line with the ideas expressed in Gould (1991) and Uriagereka (1998), is to consider uninterpretability an exaptation--a property of the language faculty that was NOT adapted for its present function, i.e. affording movement so that certain semantic effects are achieved, but later co-opted for that purpose. Uninterpretability as an adaptation must not be particularly attractive to Chomsky as it implies that uninterpretable features, which are illegible to the C-I system, are still semantically motivated in origin. Uninterpretability as an exaptation, on the other hand, makes the proposal less falsifiable than ever.

    Chapter Four The Primitives of Temporal Relations (Hamida Demirdache and Myrian Uribe-Etxebarria)

    Synopsis This article is an attempt to reduce "the grammar of Tense and Aspect to the same set of universal substantive and structural primitives" (p. 157). For Demirdache and Uribe- Etchebarria, tense relates UT-T (the time of utterance) and EV-T (the event time) with T as the head of TP with two time-denoting phrases as the arguments. T can have the meaning of WITHIN (present: UT-T WITHIN EV-T), AFTER (past: UT-T AFTER EV-T), or BEFORE (future: UT-T BEFORE EV-T). Aspect, on the other hand, is concerned with the internal temporal constituency of the event. It follows that the assertion time (AST-T) as "the time interval in the event time of the VP that Aspect focuses" (p.161) is a key term for the description of aspects. Aspect is then different from tense in that the former relates EV-T to AST-T while the latter relates AST-T to UT-T:

    TP /\ UT-T T' /\ T-0 AspP /\ AST-T Asp' /\ Asp-0 VP /\ EV-T VP

    Rejecting the Reichenbachian analyses of tense and aspect, the authors consider these spatiotemporal relations to be those of central/noncentral coincidence comparable with prepositions expressing similar spatiotemporal relations, hence:

    Central coincidence

    (a) [I ////// F] (where I and F stand for initial and final bounds of the event) e.g. Progressive

    Noncentral coincidence

    (b) //////[I F] e.g. Prospective (c) [I F]////// e.g. Perfect

    Critical evaluation The article possesses genuine theoretical merits. Moreover, the model is NOT incompatible with minimalist accounts of language. Despite that, it is not a minimalist essay in the strict sense of the word. The major thing the model has in common with minimalism is some economy flavor accompanying their Constraint on Aspect Recursion--no vacuous viewpoint shifting is allowed. Apart from this, the model seems to be more at home with Bybee, Perkins, and Pagliuca's (1994) accounts of tense and aspect. It seems to be a good example of cases where both formalist and functionalist accounts of language converge.

    Chapter Five How Far Will Quantifiers Go? (Kyle Johnson)

    Synopsis Focusing on the current accounts of Quantifier Raising (QR), Johnson tries to reveal the empirical inadequacy of the idea that QR can be reduced to A-movement (Hornstein 1995). More specifically, Hornstein suggests that both subject lowering and object raising are at work in order for the object quantifier to gain wider scope than a local subject in (1b) below:

    (1) a. [IP Someone [VP loves everyone]]. b. [IP everyone-1 [IP someone [VP loves t-1]]] c. [IP someone-2 [IP everyone-1 [IP t-2 [VP loves t-1]]]]

    He argues that on Hornstein's account an object must be narrower in scope than any other sentential element outside VP as the object moves into the first available specifier position above VP. According to Johnson, however, this is not true as (13) is still ambiguous due to *many of the questions* having wider/narrower scope that *not*:

    (13) Gary didn't answer many of the questions on the exam.

    Instead, Johnson suggests that QR is like scrambling in German and Dutch: (a) QR moves objects out of embedded infinitival clauses, (b) a complementizer in the infinitival clause blocks the operation, (c) there is no QR when the embedded clause is not infinitival, and (d) scrambling can also relocate adjuncts as QR does.

    Critical evaluation Johnson's is a genuinely minimalist analysis as it tries to collapse an operation (QR) into another independently motivated one (scrambling). Despite that, it is not clear why QR must prove to be similar to this specific operation and nothing else.

    For Chomsky, movement--an imperfection of language--takes place in the fulfillment of certain morphological requirements - uninterpretable features; another imperfection of language. While the existence of some morphological constraints on scrambling is NOT inconceivable after all, it does not necessarily mean that scrambling is morphologically motivated in the Chomskyan sense of the word. Johnson's analysis raises certain expectations with regard to some common (morphological) source for both QR and scrambling, which are not satisfied in this article. Even at the level of constraints, it is not clear at all how QR and scrambling can share featural characteristics. Then Johnson's analysis fails to go beyond a mere analogy drawn between QR and scrambling. It seems to be far from "collapsing" one operation to another.

    Chapter Six Japanese Complex Noun Phrases and the Antisymmetry Theory (Keiko S. Murasugi)

    Synopsis Japanese "relative clauses" are known to have very peculiar properties. Murasugi argues that relative clauses are not allowed in the language. Instead, the language employs pure sentential modifiers to modify the nominal heads extensively, and, as a result, can express relative clause meaning via pure complex NPs. But why is it so?

    Kayne (1994) proposes the structure in (1) below for N-final relative clauses derived by (a) the movement of the relative head to [Spec, CP], and (b) the movement of IP to [Spec, DP].

    (1) [DP [IP ... t-i ...]-j [D' D [CP NP-i [C' C t-j]]]]

    Movement to [Spec, CP] is in general A-bar movement. As a result, it proves to be a violation of the Proper Binding Condition, which is not allowed in Japanese "relative clauses" due to the finiteness of their main verbs. Relative clauses are simply impossible in Japanese because of this nonmovement property of Japanese "relatives".

    Critical evaluation Murasugi's chapter is quite well-organized, empirically rich and theoretically intriguing. Her use of the evidence from child Japanese to support her theory-internal analysis is especially interesting. The essay is not minimalist in the strict sense of the term, however. It is written within the principles-and-parameters general framework with heavy reliance on Kayne's Antisymmetry Theory. No use is made of other concepts and mechanisms recurrent in the standard minimalist literature such as those introduced in Chomsky (1993-2000). The article is unique in that it is the only essay in this collection with no single reference to Chomsky's work.

    Chapter Seven A Conspiracy Theory of Case and Agreement (Javier Ormazabal)

    Synopsis Ormazabal focuses on the relation between case checking and movement. Perlmutter (1971) had already noticed the well- formed combination of clitics in Romance as 1DAT+3ACC and how it contrasted with the ill-formed 3DAT+1ACC. Ormazabal also notices the well-formed 1ABS+3DAT in Basque, contra Bonet's (1994) descriptive generalization according to which if DAT, then ACC/ABS = 3rd person.

    Two competing proposals--Albizu's (1997) morphological analysis (Person-Case Constraint) and the Minimal Link Condition (MLC)--are examined to find out how well each of them accounts for such cooccurrence restrictions. Ormazabal finds Albizu's account conceptually redundant, and favors a syntactic account in terms of the MLC. Based on some empirical evidence from Romance, which reveals a contrast between strong and weak pronouns, he concludes that it is the feature [+animate], and not Case, that can explain such phenomena. "[T]he movement of arguments from the VP shell is not driven by Case-checking considerations, but by the need to check an animacy feature: only [+animate] arguments are forced to move from their base-generated position" (p.248).

    Critical evaluation Ormazabal's interesting empirical evidence for the role [+animate] plays in movement raises questions on the sustainability of minimalist thesis of movement and also checking theory. In standard minimalist accounts, it is an uninterpretable feature that is typically checked and finally deleted to prevent crash at interface levels. Actually Chomsky (this volume) collapses these two so-called imperfections of language, namely uninterpretability and dislocation, into one so that the former brings about the latter. Now Ormazabal tells us that it is not an uninterpretable feature that initiates movement but the interpretable [+animate]: "unlike syntactic Case, which is a theory- internal construct, features like [+animate] point to a conception of checking operations where the feature checked is interpretable in either the target or the attracted element, and it survives to one of the interface levels" (p.254).

    The proposal boils down to the claim that movement takes place after all in the fulfillment of some checking requirement, which is not a challenge to Chomsky's thesis of movement. The point of departure from the standard theories of movement then proves to be the status of the feature (to be checked) in terms of interpretability. This raises two problems for Ormazabal's account, one conceptual, and the other technical. For Chomsky, interpretable features need not be checked (1995:289) because it is always the uninterpretable feature that is an illegitimate object at interface levels, hence to be checked and deleted. But for Ormazabal the urge for checking [+animate] is so compelling that checking this interpretable feature via movement becomes a forced move. The conceptual question is what this checking is after all that forces such a move. If checking is not the deletion of an uninterpretable in order to prevent the crash of the derivation at interface levels, what is it? The technical problem is that in his examples for animacy effects, it must be the [+animate] feature of the moved element (the strong pronoun/1st and 2nd person pronouns) that is always checked through movement rather than that of the target: in the grammatical sentences with a cliticized pronoun (which does not exhibit the [+animate] feature) the [+animate] feature of the target (if there is such a feature there after all) is necessarily left unchecked due to the absence of any other element with the [+animate] feature to do the checking. This is more compatible with Chomsky's (now outdated) formulation of Greed as here alpha moves to satisfy its own checking requirements. Then Ormazabal's use of the term "attracted element" is rather odd.

    Chapter Eight The Japanese Light Verb Construction and the Minimalist Program (Mamoru Saito and Hiroto Hoshi)

    Synopsis In a Japanese light verb construction one or more arguments of the theta-assigning noun appear as clausal arguments of the non-theta-assigning light verb *su* while the others remain within the projection of the noun:

    (1) Mary-ga John-ni [NP toti-no zyooto]-o sita. Mary-NOM John-to land-GEN giving-ACC did 'Mary gave a piece of land to John.'

    According to Grimshaw and Mester's (1988) argument transfer analysis, the noun *zyooto* 'giving' transfers its agent (Mary) and goal (John) theta-roles to the verb *sita* (= su + ta 'past') while the theme argument *toti* 'land' remains within the NP headed by the theta-role-assigning noun. They note the following restrictions on such constructions:

    (2) a. At least one internal theta-role of the noun must be assigned to an argument outside the NP. b. If a theta-role T is assigned outside the NP, then all theta-roles that are higher than T in the thematic hierarchy must also be assigned outside the NP.

    Saito and Hoshi believe that this analysis "is a description of a fact rather than an explanation" (p.273). Moreover, "it is not clear why the thematic hierarchy must be observed, after argument transfer takes place, among the arguments of two independent theta-role assigners" (p.274) namely the theta-role assigning noun and the light verb *su*. Instead they argue for an LF incorporation analysis in which the noun *zyooto* is assumed to assign its theme theta-role within the NP and then raise to the position of *su* in LF and discharge its agent and goal theta-roles there. This new analysis supports Chomsky's (1995) minimalist program according to which D-Structure, S-Structure and the Projection Principle are eliminated. It also favors the Last Resort condition on movement.

    Critical evaluation While the criticisms Saito and Hoshi level at Grimshaw and Mester's argument transfer analysis are not unreasonable, it is somehow doubtful that their own LF incorporation analysis is not a more abstract and less accessible description of the same facts that Grimshaw and Mester's analysis tries to capture. That theta-roles are formal features of the theta-assigners which enter checking relations is apparently a descriptive label itself rather than a genuine explanation of why things work that way. Actually what Grimshaw and Mester assume to have taken place at the abstract and invisible interface level of D-Structure is now shifted in position to another interface level equally abstract and invisible. Although the analysis helps to dispense with D-Structure, it does so at the price of interpreting theta roles after Spell-Out in positions different from the base. The conceptual problem is that this makes PF-LF mapping increasingly difficult to explain. In Grimshaw and Mester's analysis, on the other hand, the transfer takes place at D-Structure, hence a part of the common heritage of PF and LF.

    Chapter Nine Move F and Raising of Lexical and Empty DPs (Daiko Takahashi)

    Synopsis The major question Takahashi addresses in this essay is why a category alpha (and not some feature F to be checked) must move into the checking domain. As Takahashi put it, Chomsky (1995) assumes two conditions with regard to the movement of F:

    (1) F carries along just enough material for convergence. (2) Words whose features are isolated or scattered may not be subject to PF rules, making the derivation crash.

    Condition (2), or Takahashi's PF Integrity Condition, makes two predictions. First, "since the PF Integrity Condition is simply inapplicable in LF, LF movement should be restricted to feature movement" (p.298). Second, "if alpha, a category containing a feature F that is about to enter into a checking relation, is phonologically null ..., then movement of F alone out of alpha should be possible ... . This leads to the expectation that other things being equal, empty categories should behave differently from their lexical counterparts when they contain features that need to undergo checking" (p.298). In this chapter Takahashi uses the data from a raising construction in Japanese to confirm the second prediction.

    (1) F carries along just enough material for convergence. (2) Words whose features are isolated or scattered may not be subject to PF rules, making the derivation crash.

    Condition (2), or Takahashi's PF Integrity Condition, makes two predictions. First, "since the PF Integrity Condition is simply inapplicable in LF, LF movement should be restricted to feature movement" (p. 298). Second, "if alpha, a category containing a feature F that is about to enter into a checking relation, is phonologically null ..., then movement of F alone out of alpha should be possible ... . This leads to the expectation that other things being equal, empty categories should behave differently from their lexical counterparts when they contain features that need to undergo checking" (p. 298). In this chapter Takahashi uses the data from a raising construction in Japanese to confirm the second prediction.

    There are two types of empty pronominal subjects in Japanese: one type is called argumental pro as it receives a theta-role, and is exemplified in (3) below (his 8); the other is quasi-argumental pro as it does not bear any theta- role (e.g. in (4) below (his 16):

    (3) pro Hanako-o sikatta. Hanako-ACC scolded 'I/WE/You/He/She/They scolded Hanako.'

    (4) pro sigureta. rained 'It rained.'

    Takahashi observes that quasi-argumental pros cannot raise while argumental ones behave like lexical DPs. Consequently, argumental pros raise to control PRO while quasi-argumental ones cannot:

    (5) pro-1 [PRO-1 biiru-o nomi nagara] Hanako-o sikari beer-ACC drinking while Hanako-ACC scolding hazimeta. began 'I/We/You/He/She/They began scolding Hanako while drinking beer.' (with the meaning that at some point during drinking beer, I/we/you/he/she/they began scolding Hanako)

    (6)* pro-1 [PRO-1 sigure nagara] t-1 fubuki hazimeta. raining while snowing began 'It began snowing while raining.' (with the meaning that at some point during the rainfall, snow began to fall)

    Based on this asymmetry in raising between these non- argumental pros and their lexical counterparts, Takahashi argues that the asymmetry follows from the Move F hypothesis. Apparently, the raised F lacks some qualification necessary to control. The other possibility is that features cannot control at all. Whatever the case, it confirms the second prediction as null subjects (quasi-argumental pros) differ from their lexical counterparts in raising. "Although argumental pros appear not to conform to the prediction of (the) ... analysis, ... they do not undermine it, since the seemingly unexpected cases may not involve raising at all" (p.314).

    Critical evaluation The central question here seems to be why the feature F contained in the element alpha cannot raise without the PF material pied-piped to it *prior to Spell-Out* as raising F without the PF material at LF is already taken to be borne out in the literature Takahashi mentions in his chapter. Takahashi's focus on null subjects is an attempt to control this extraneous factor of PF features. He correctly hypothesizes that under such circumstances "the movement of F alone out of alpha should be ... obligatory ... even in overt syntax" (p. 298) as empty categories have no PF features at all to be pied-piped to their formal features. As a result, one expects the feature F of a null subject to raise when needed without making the sentence ungrammatical. However, it is not quite clear how Takahashi takes the impossibility of raising quasi-argumental pros to support the hypothesis that a phonetically null element may have its formal features raised. On the contrary, this could mean that a quasi-argumental pro (nor one of its formal features) can raise in overt syntax even if no PF features are pied- piped to it. (6) above (with the interpretation specified) is ungrammatical NOT because features cannot control but that they do not get scattered/isolated even then. In other words, argumental pros, quasi-argumental pros and lexical DPs disallow some formal feature of themselves to raise on its own. They differ in that DPs and argumental pros raise while quasi-argumental ones don't.

    Chapter Ten On the Grammar of Polish Nominals (Ewa Willim)

    Synopsis Willim investigates the relevance of the DP analysis of nominal structure to the grammar of nominals in Polish, an articleless language with rich nominal inflection for gender, number, and morphological case. The empirical data, including the absence of lexical articles, and no clitic attaching to the genitive subject, Willim concludes that "there is neither functional morphology to support the functional head D in Polish, nor evidence for a phonologically unrealized but syntactically active D head in the language" (p.330).

    In languages with the D paradigm, extraction from NP takes place via [Spec, DP] so that features can be checked in the configuration headed by D. It follows that such extractions are sensitive to the Specificity Condition. Willim again find no direct evidence on the availability of D as "a head providing a position targeted by a phrase undergoing overt movement in Polish" (p.332).

    Longobardi (1994) assumes that the feature [+/- R] marks the element in D position. For proper nouns and pronouns the value of the feature is positive as they refer to objects. In Italian, [+R] is strong while "[i]n English [+R] is weak, banning overt N-to-D raising ..." (p.337). Empirical data from Bemba and Basque suggest that (in)definiteness of reference is not the function of D. It follows that the existence of the DP layer at LF is not logically necessary for Polish nominals. "Rather, (in)definiteness of reference may be directly related to the properties of syntactic configurations in which nominals find themselves at LF in Polish" (p.340).

    Critical evaluation To my relief, Willim does NOT conclude that although DP is missing in Polish overt syntax, there is some DP projection at its LF so that the highest level of generalizability is guaranteed for our minimalist theories and mechanisms! Although Willim does not dismiss LF as the level at which (in)definiteness and also the reference of nominals are determined, she rejects the necessity of resorting to D-insertion at LF and also the existence of some DP layer there for doing such things. Instead, the properties of LF syntactic configurations in which nominals (and not Ds) are inserted will suffice.

    References Albizu, P. 1997. Generalized Person-Case Constraint: A case for a syntax-driven inflectional morphology. In A. Mendikoetxea and M. Uribe-Etxebarria, eds. Theoretical Issues on the Morphology-Syntax Interface, 1-34. ASJU, San Sebastian.

    Bonet, E. 1994. The Person-Case Constraint: A morphological approach. In H. Harley and C. Phillips, eds. The Morphology- Syntax Connection, 32-52.

    Bybee, J., R. Perkins, and W. Pagliuca. 1994. The evolution of grammar: Tense, aspect, and modality in the languages of the world. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Chomsky, N. 1981. Lectures on Government and Binding. Dordrecht: Foris.

    Chomsky, N. 1995. The Minimalist Program. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.

    Cinque, G. 1990. Types of A-bar Dependencies. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.

    Gould, S. J. 1991. Exaptation: A crucial tool for evolutionary psychology. Journal of Social Issues 47, 43-65.

    Grimshaw, J. and A. Mester. 1988. Light verbs and theta- marking. Linguistic Inquiry 19, 205-232.

    Higginbotham, J. and R. May. 1981. Questions, quantifiers, and crossing. The Linguistic Review 1. 41-80.

    Huang, C-T. J. 1982. Logical relations in Chinese and the theory of grammar. Doctoral dissertation, MIT, Cambridge, Mass.

    Kayne, R. 1994. The Antisymmetry of Syntax. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.

    Lasnik, H., and M. Saito. 1984. On the nature of proper government. Linguistic Inquiry 15, 235-289.

    Lasnik, H., and M. Saito. 1992. Move Alpha. Cambridge, Mass,: MIT Press.

    Longobardi, G. 1994. Reference and proper names. Linguistic Inquiry 25, 609-665.

    Lotfi, A. R. (ms.) Semantico-Phonetic Form: A unitariainist grammar. Available on Arizona Minimalist Syntax Archives at <http://www.minimalism.linguistics.arizona.edu/AMSA/PDF/ AMSA-186-1200.txt>.

    Perlmutter, D. 1971. Deep and Surface Structure Constraints in Syntax. New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston.

    Pesetsky, D. 1987. Wh-in-situ: Movement and unselective binding. In E. Reuland and A. ter Meulon, eds., The Representation of (In)Definiteness. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.

    Reinhart, T. 1995. Interface strategies. (OST Working Papers of Theoretical Linguistics 95-002.) Utrecht Institute of Linguistics OTS, Utrecht University.

    Uriagereka, J. 1998. Rhyme and Reason: An Introduction to Minimalist Syntax. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.

    Reviewer: Dr. Ahmad R. Lotfi, Chair of the English Department, Azad University at Esfahan, Iran, where he teaches linguistics to graduate students of ELT. His research interests lie in minimalist syntax, second language acquisition studies in generative grammar, and Persian linguistics.