LINGUIST List 13.112

Fri Jan 18 2002

Review: The Minimalist Parameter

Editor for this issue: Terence Langendoen <terrylinguistlist.org>


What follows is another discussion note contributed to our Book Discussion Forum. We expect these discussions to be informal and interactive; and the author of the book discussed is cordially invited to join in.

If you are interested in leading a book discussion, look for books announced on LINGUIST as "available for discussion." (This means that the publisher has sent us a review copy.) Then contact Simin Karimi at siminlinguistlist.org or Terry Langendoen at terrylinguistlist.org.

Subscribe to Blackwell's LL+ at http://www.linguistlistplus.com/ and donate 20% of your subscription to LINGUIST! You get 30% off on Blackwells books, and free shipping and postage!


Directory

  • Sharbani Banerji, Review: Alexandrova and Arnaudova, The Minimalist Parameter

    Message 1: Review: Alexandrova and Arnaudova, The Minimalist Parameter

    Date: Thu, 17 Jan 2002 15:48:44 +0530
    From: Sharbani Banerji <sharbevsnl.net>
    Subject: Review: Alexandrova and Arnaudova, The Minimalist Parameter


    Alexandrova, Galina M., and Olga Arnaudova, ed. (2001) The Minimalist Parameter: Selected Papers from the Open Linguistics Forum, Ottawa, 21-23 March 1997. John Benjamins Publishing Company, hardback ISBN 1-55619-970-8, viii+360pp, $87.00, Current Issues in Linguistic Theory 192.

    Sharbani Banerji, Centre for Applied Linguistics and Translation Studies, University Of Hyderabad, India.

    DESCRIPTION OF THE BOOK This volume is a collection of twenty papers, addressing a range of issues of the Minimalist Program, particularly of Chomsky (1995). The articles, as the editors point out, have been derived from papers read at the "Challenges of Minimalism" session of the Open Linguistic Forum (OLF), held in Ottawa, 21-23 March 1997.

    Each paper in this book addresses some issue or other, which needs to be reviewed or updated under the 'Minimalist Program', or brings forth issues which have perhaps been overlooked in the past, and now are being treated under 'Minimalism'. Some of the papers work elaborately to point out the advantages of working in the framework of Chomsky (1995) as against Chomsky (1981), or even Chomsky (1992). Kayne's (1994) work is a part of this program, and hence a paper devoted to this framework is included. The book, being technical in nature, will be best appreciated by students, researchers and professionals working in the Minimalist Program. Those working in different frameworks, may use it for comparative purposes.

    The book is broadly divided into five sections. Each section represents the area covered by the papers of that section. Section I (Syntactic Structure, Relations, Operations) consists of six papers, Section II (Syntactic Movement: Cyclicity, Optionality, (Non) overtness) five papers, Section III (Case, Topic, Focus, Interrogativity) also five papers, Section IV (Ellipsis, Reconstruction and Related Phenomena) two papers and Section V (DPs: Features and Syntactic Relations) also two papers. The references pertaining each of the papers is given at the end of each paper.

    What follows is a brief description of each of the twenty papers, to indicate what their aims and objectives are, and what they finally show. Some of the papers are followed by a brief evaluative comment. A short critical evaluation of the volume as a whole is given at the end of the review.

    SECTION I: Syntactic Structure, Relations, Operations 1) Integral Minimalism, by Denis Bouchard Given the central role of Principles and Parameters in current theorizing, it is it is important to ascertain what is an optimal principle and an optimal parameter on general grounds. The situation should be such that i) some element is required by conceptual necessity, is expected to be part of the human faculty, and ii) there is more than one way to satisfy this requirement, given bare output conditions imposed from outside. The author refers to this restrictive approach as 'Integral Minimalism'.

    Basic assumptions of Integral Minimalism: i) The only structural primitives are lexical items and an associative function Merge that combines them.

    ii) It follows from the underspecification of the operation Merge that the merger of a and b is licensed by selectional properties: if the complex expression resulting from combining a and b cannot be interpreted by the rules of the language, the result is gibberish (i.e., human languages combine meaningful elements into larger ones). Typically, one of a or b is a functor category which the other one saturates or modifies by assigning a property to it.

    iii) Since the only primitives available are those taken from the lexicon, the result of merging a and b is labelled 'a' or 'b', not some additional label (labels like 'N', 'A', 'P' are used only for convenience; they have no status in the theory and are just abbreviations).

    iv) The functor category is the one that projects; the idea is that, even though a category X is slightly changed, since it is saturated or modified by it's sister category, it remains essentially X.

    Thus, very minimal differences account for functional covariation between phrasal-structural languages, morphologically marking languages, and sign languages. This also accounts for variation among phrasal languages like French and English.

    2) A Minimalist Account of Phrase Structure Acquisition, by Susan Powers This paper compares two accounts of the phenomenon of gradual phrase structure acquisition developed in the Government and Binding (GB) framework with one based on the Minimalist Program. The minimalist account of phrase structure acquisition is argued to be more viable for reasons of economy and empirical coverage.

    The GB acquisition accounts are versions of the No Functional Projections Hypothesis, which maintains that only phrase markers of the lexical heads (N, V, A, P) are part of the child's initial phrase marker system. The UG-given X-bar component generates phrase structure. While the child's phrase marker system is a subset of the adult, it is not minimal enough. Even lexical projections contain more phrase structure positions than are necessary to accommodate the earliest utterances.

    An acquisition account, where (in view of minimalist assumptions) the single operation of Merge builds phrase structure, captures the acquisition sequence much more accurately. The first stage in development is a lexical stage, in which syntactic categories are identified. At the subsequent stage, the syntactic objects from the first stage are merged into simple binary trees. As soon as the child treats these phrase markers as objects, these are merged into more complex structures.

    The proposed approach to phrase structure acquisition is superior to the GB tree-building accounts, as there are no extraneous positions in the phrase marker. Moreover, structure-building via Merge can elegantly capture the graduality observed in development. Under this minimalist account, the phrase marker gradually expands due to successive applications of Merge. In this way, the stages in the acquisition sequence reflect intermediate steps in the derivation.

    The arguments strike me as convincing.

    3) A Theory of Grammatical Functions in the Minimalist Program, by Hiroyuki Ura In this paper the author attempts to explore a theory of Grammatical Functions (GF) under the framework of the Minimalist Program outlined in Chomsky (1995). The main purpose of the paper is to demonstrate that the theory of multiple F(eature) -checking gives a natural explanation of a wide range of data found in a variety of languages in a very consistent way, with a limited set of parameters. The main idea is that each GF results from a particular checking relation. More specifically control results from a phi -checking relation with T and binding of a subject-oriented reflexive from an EPP checking relation with T. Since there are many other kinds of GFs in natural language, it is necessary to investigate how the various kinds of checking relation determine the type of GF.

    In the GB theory, grammatical relations (GRs) were regarded not as absolute but as a derivative (cf. Chomsky 1981 and Marantz 1984), following Chomsky's 1965 idea that they should be structurally derived/defined, and the widely held assumption was that an argument with a particular GR assumes particular functions in syntactic respects.

    >From the view point of Chomsky's (1994, 1995) Minimalism, the structural determination of GRs and GFs is conceptually problematic, because no structural relations can be defined in a uniform and absolute fashion any longer owing to the abandonment of the 'conventional' X-bar theory in view of its lack of conceptual necessity. Thus the conceptual basis of the definition of GRs and GFs is lost and the question arises as to how these relations and functions can be defined in the Chomskian Minimalist theory.

    Proposal: Each type of GF is determined by a particular checking relation. Specifically:

    1) The ability to control a missing argument in a subordinate adjunct clause results from a phi -checking relation with T-which means that the ability to induce subject agreement should be linked to a phi -checking relation with V.

    2) The ability to bind a (purely) subject-oriented reflexive, which has been linked to the GR subject, results from an EPP-relation with T.

    To give a Minimalist explanation to GF-splitting, the author relies crucially on the system of 'multiple feature checking', an extension of Chomksy's (1995) F-checking theory.

    The case studies undertaken are: i) Japanese Dative subject constructions ii) Imbabura Quechua Passive iii) Active/Inverse voice alternation in Navajo

    A lucid paper, which I enjoyed reading.

    4) Checking on 'Checking', by Sharon Armon-Lotem This paper proposes that Checking is a unified process applying only after Spell-Out. This challenges the assumption that 'strong' features should be checked prior to Spell-Out, whereas other features are checked only after Spell-Out(Chomsky 1995). To make this proposal feasible, a way to compute the 'strength' of functional heads at PF is offered. A clear distinction is drawn between lexical and functional categories (Grimshaw 1991), suggesting that lexical categories are fully specified for all their features, whereas functional categories are endowed with unspecified features. By a computing mechanism (value sharing), the head features of the functional head are specified: an extended head shares the values of the features of the lexical head after a lexical phrase marker and a functional one are merged into an extended projection.

    The maximal set of features that can be associated with some functional head in some particular language is compared with the set of features which are shared with the lexical head in that particular derivation. When the two sets are equal, the head manifests properties of a strong head, but when there is a mismatch between them, the head manifests properties of a weak head. The identification of matching feature sets, i.e., of 'strong' heads, is attributed to the PF component, where a fully specified functional head needs to be associated with a lexical item.

    Assigning overt movement to PF limits checking to LF. Various implications for lexical learning and language acquisition are discussed in this paper.

    5) Kayne 1994: p. 143, fn. 3, by John Whitman In the footnote that provided the title of this article, Kayne recommends investigating the possibility that the Nominative marker 'ga' and topic marker 'wa' and possibly the accusative marker 'o' in Japanese head projections taking complements to their right. This paper is devoted to an exploration of the hypothesis that these and certain other phrase particles head projections with complements to their right.

    Kayne (1994) argues effectively against the existence of syntactic projections whose complements intervene between Head and Spec, a configuration that has long been assumed across categories for languages like Korean and Japanese.

    The discussion to follow investigates an approach to constituent order in head-final languages such as Japanese and Korean. This approach provides an explanation for the failure of Nominative subject constructions in Japanese to undergo scrambling or clefting. It leads to the conclusion that multiple Nom subject constructions in Japanese are recursively headed structures. The final section of the paper explores the relationship between movement and head position, and suggests a possible direction for a theory of word order based on 'shallow' constituent relations such as adjacency, rather than structural relations such as c-command.

    The core of the analysis has been the idea that a class of phonological dependents which have long been understood to function as markers of clause type (or in the case of the genitive, phrase type), are actually phrasal heads. This analysis leads to a rethinking of the syntax of the multiple Spec constructions characteristic of Korean and Japanese, and suggests an explanation for restriction on Scrambling, Clefting and Subjectivization.

    6) On the Role of Interpretability, by Masanori Nakamura There are two major (obviously related) ways in which the notion of 'interpretability' plays a role in the current version of Minimalism. First, it is important in the principle of Full interpretation (FI) (Chomsky 1986), which requires that LF representations consist only of 'legitimate' (i.e., interpretable) objects. Second, as argued by Chomsky 1995, it plays a crucial role in F(eature) checking operations, in which [-Int(erpretable)] features are effectively eliminated (in order to obtain well formed LF representations), whereas [+Int(erpretable)] features can be accessed more than once. To examine whether the notion proves essential in other domains as well, the present paper focuses on 'it-type' CP expletives which, lacking semantic content, are of interest from the viewpoint of FI. An analysis of 'it-type' expletives is put forth, where they are 'replaced' by their associates in covert syntax. It is shown to solve two puzzles regarding the interactions between CP expletives and wh-movement, one from Bahasa Indonesia/Malaysia, and the other from German. It also leads to the claim that the concept of Interpretability plays an important role in the theory of economy. More specifically, it is suggested that the concept enters into the determination of the 'reference set' and, possibly, the application of economy conditions. To the extent the analysis is correct, the notion of Interpretability is even more significant than is recognized in Chomsky (1995).

    Section II: Syntactic Movement: Cyclicity, Optionality, (Non) Overtness 1) Head-to-Spec Movement, by Takashi Toyoshima Since Emonds' (1970) proposal, substitution movement is taken generally to be structure preserving. This Structure-Preservation Hypothesis (SPH) has been supplemented by generalizing an X'-format to functional categories, and it is further extended to adjunction movement (Chomsky 1986). In the Minimalist Program of Chomsky (1992, 1994, 1995), theory- internal constructs such as D-structure and S-structure are abandoned and the generative procedure itself is conceived of as phrase structure building processes. Thus, there is no structure to preserve. Yet, the assumption that all movements are structure preserving has persisted into the Minimalist Program, even after its abandonment of the X'- Schema entirely (Chomsky 1994). In particular, it is scarcely observed for head-to-head adjunction, although all the other movements are not structure preserving anymore, even from the traditional perspective.

    In this paper it is argued that all movements are to a Specifier position, in particular, that there should be no head-to-head adjunction, but rather, head movement is to a specifier position. This Head-to-Spec movement eliminates various problems associated with head- to-head adjunction and also dispenses with various stipulations which head-to-head adjunction would necessitate. The segment/category distinction is eliminated, and 'contiguity' of the checking domain is achieved.

    2) Polish Optional Movement, by Adam Szczegielniak In this paper, the author studies the nature of Optional Movement(OM) in Polish. In simple transitive clauses, Polish exhibits free word order: Six word orders are allowed (SVO, SOV, OSV, OVS, VSO, VOS), all of which can be produced with the same non-Topic/Focus stress pattern. (It is assumed that Topic/Focus manifests itself by having a special stress pattern. Some of the variations are more natural with special Topic/Focus stress). Polish has an SVO basic order. Also, the fact that it is a prepositional language indicates that it is head-initial.

    It is argued that Polish Optional movement(POM) is not an instance of one single operation termed 'scrambling', but instead is a combination of F(eature) and non-F(eature)-checking movement. The latter obligatorily reconstructs to the last F-checking position, and, with the exception of WCO effects, behaves like movement to a non-L-related position. It is also shown that the distinction between broadly and narrowly L-related positions can be abandoned for POM. The claim is that POM is purely EPP driven and, although, it can result in features being checked, it does not have to. Thus, unlike in Japanese and German OM, Polish has no semantically interpretable scrambling feature. This is supported by a contrastive analysis of OM semantics and economy of movement properties. Finally, it is proposed that it is possible to incorporate overt non-F-checking movement into the Minimalist framework, provided functional heads can be parametrized not only for violations of Procrastinate (as in Ura 1996), but also for last resort. This is achieved by postulating that the interaction of +/-interpretable features on heads with [EPP] is subject to parametric variation. The claim being that in POM [EPP] is completely dissociated from formal/semantic features.

    An interesting paper, especially for those working on scrambling languages.

    3) Attract AND Covert Merge: Predicting Interrogative Variation, by Bernadette Plunkett In this paper the author develops a minimalist account of the parametric variation between wh-questions (wh-qs) in French and English. Much work in the GB tradition was dedicated to the explanation of the parametric variation found in wh-constructions. Rizzi's (1991) approach to questions in English and French invoking the wh-criterion, was widely adopted and adapted to explain the behaviour of questions in other languages, since it succeeded in dealing with a considerable amount of variation.

    The move to a minimalist model of syntax (Chomsky1995) raises several problems for an updating of this kind of approach. Rizzi's model has two characteristics which are incompatible with the most recent view of Minimalist principles. The first is that his version of the Wh- criterion is two pronged, necessitating that wh-features on both a WhP(hrase) and a functional head have independent checking requirements. The second, which relates to the first, is the use of Dynamic Agreement to explain non-inverted questions in French; this requires the XP to move without attraction by a head.

    In this paper the author develops a Minimalist account of the parametric variation between wh-qs in French and English, which dispenses with Dynamic agreement and invokes only a single pronged wh- criterion, based on an approach to movement which relies solely on Attract.

    Interrogatives vary cross-linguistically along the following three axes. WhPs in French and English vary across the first two.

    i) overt vs. (covert movement) of WhPs. ii) Inversion vs. non-inversion of verb and subject iii) Movement of one WhP vs. all WhPs.

    In Plunkett (1996) it was proposed that an essential difference between French and English was the presence in French, but not in English, of root complementisers. In circumstances where root [+wh] Comps are not available (English) or not selected in the numeration (French), the author assumes with Rizzi1991 that wh-features are associated with an inflectional head (in the root case call it T) and that the presence of the Wh-features on T rather than on C is what is responsible for 'inversion'. If clauses can be of different types (e.g., Small Clauses, AgrsP, TPs or CPs), it is natural to expect Wh-features to appear on the 'head' of any clause in the scope of which a WhP is to be interpreted. Thus, since clauses are not always CPs, wh-features shouldnot be exclusively associated with C. Assuming this modification, it is predicted that where root complementisers are projected, [wh] will appear on C, otherwise they will appear on an inflectional head in the matrix. In this case, if the subject fills the specifier position of the clausal head, the head will need to raise to check its wh- features, except if the subject itself is [+wh].

    The proposals here centre on two new ideas which are compatible with Minimalism -- Covert Merge and the creation of proxy projections for multiple feature checking. Unmoved WhPs in wh-movement languages are attributed to the possibility of merging non-overt heads after Spell out. Uninverted questions in French are treated as involving a [+wh] Comp. Inversion structures involve proxy projections. Proxy structures arise from the adjunction of a head to its own projection allowing the otherwise impossible projection-internal checking of more than one strong feature. Variation in interrogative structures across French and English is treated as being due to one essential difference, the availability of root complementisers.

    A rather heavy paper theoretically.

    4) Covert F(eature)-Movement and the Placement of Arguments, by Artemis Alexiadou and Elena Anagnostopoulou In this paper the authors investigate the syntactic conditions on the placement of postverbal subjects in transitive and intransitive constructions in representatives of Germanic and Romance, and argue that there is a constraint against leaving multiple arguments VP- internally. They attribute this constraint to a ban against multiple covert F(eature) -movement to a single head containing more than one unchecked feature of the same type.

    The syntactic conditions on the placement of postverbal subjects in Germanic and Romance (Italian/Catalan) provide evidence for the following two generalizations:

    a) Postverbal subjects are severely restricted in transitive constructions but not in intransitive ones.

    b) There is a cross-linguistic variation in the availability of subject-inverted orders in transitive constructions but a certain degree of uniformity in intransitive constructions.

    They show that if a language permits subject movement to T and/or O(bject)-shift, VP internal subjects will be possible in the presence of an object (e.g., Icelandic; Catalan). Otherwise the language will show an intransitivity constraint on subject-inverted orders (English, Mainland Scandinavian).

    Transitive Expletive Constructions(TECs) are one environment where postverbal subjects occur. TECs are possible in Icelandic, German and Dutch and impossible in English and mainland Scandinavian.

    In Icelandic it is found that TECs occur with VP-external subjects and VP external/internal objects. In English, it is a well known observation that TECs are impossible, i.e., subject inverted orders are allowed only with certain classes of intransitive verbs (both unergatives and unaccusatives). Postverbal subjects are found in subject-inverted orders in Romance. Specifically, VSO orders are impossible in Italian and Catalan, both of which permit only VOS with VP-internal subjects and scrambled objects. Similarly in Catalan.

    A number of people have provided strong evidence that VOS orders involve leftward movement of the object over the subject. The facts show that, in the languages under discussion, it is never the case that both DP arguments can remain VP-internally. Two proposals are considered:

    A) One could assume that a (PF/LF) filter banning multiple VP-internal arguments is at work here.

    B) There is a constraint against multiple covert case driven movement.

    A) cannot hold because PPs can remain VP-internally, and in double object constructions, the Theme argument remains VP-internal in the presence of a VP-internal subject. Thus, option B is chosen:

    That is, there is a constraint against covert movement of both SUBJECT and OBJECT. The authors distinguish between D-feature of I, which is identified as the EPP feature, and the N-feature of I, which is identified as the Case feature. Thus in TECs, the expletive checks the D-feature (EPP) and the subject the N-feature (Case). Ambiguity arises only when there are multiple N (=case) features. Thus it seems to be the case that Attract is sensitive to the category of features attracted and not to the specific value of the features, i.e., Nominative vs. Accusative etc.

    5) On Covert Movement and LF, by Andrew Simpson In this paper, the author questions the necessity of LF as a syntactically distinct, derivational level, in the current Minimalist model of syntax. Hence, to present his arguments, he first reviews the earlier theories on LF, presenting the motivations for LF in those models, starting from GB to the present day Minimalism (Chomsky 1995). Specifically, he discusses the changing conception of covert movement and LF in the GB model, in Chomsky (1993) and in Chomsky 1995. Many empirical arguments put forward in the GB period as justification for assuming the existence of an abstract but syntactic level of LF can no longer be considered valid support for the continued existence of LF within MP due to a number of conceptual changes proposed in the latter. With the process of change, he argues that the earlier strong empirically based arguments for assuming a syntactic distinct level of LF have lost their validity. If the principle motivation for LF in the Minimalist program (MP) is only an assumption of 'uniformity' in licensing certain types of elements which cross-linguistically are taken to require licensing in a universal way, then, 'the uniformity hypothesis' itself can be questioned, and possibly disproved. The author draws his conclusions based on a paradigm of wh- and Neg(ation) related data. The data is taken from Iraqi Arabic, Hindi and Japanese. The same data is analysed in the GB model, in Chomsky (1993) and Chomsky (1995) models respectively, and he shows how such an analysis would be untenable. He then shows how the data previously accounted for via covert movement may be handled in a model WITHOUT any level of LF. He shows how the licensing of elements with weak features might be treated in such a model without a level of LF.

    It is proposed that a natural and positive progression consequently open to the MP is therefore to dispense with the notion of LF as a discrete syntactic level formed by applications of Move and to assume that Spell-Out is instead the endpoint of dynamic syntax. Finally, it is considered how such a goal may be achieved while retaining an account of cross-linguistic variation previously captured in more standard models employing LF movement.

    The paper is a theoretically enlightening paper, though more empirical support is needed for justification.

    Section III: Case, Topic, Focus, Interrogativity 1) The Case Filter Meets the Minimalist Program: Evidence for Strong [Case], by Julie Anne Legate and Carolyn Smallwood This paper challenges the minimalist position explicit in Chomsky (1995), namely, that the EPP reduces to the D-feature of T. It is argued that the feature [D] is insufficient to account for the range of cross-linguistic variation found among human languages. The authors examine English expletive constructions, Icelandic transitive expletive constructions (TECs), and Irish subjectless clauses, and demonstrate that there is considerable variation in the realization of EPP in these languages. Subsequently, they reject Chomsky's multiple checking account of Icelandic Transitive Expletives as theoretically undesirable and empirically inadequate.

    As an alternative to Chomsky's proposal, it is claimed that two features, [D] and [case] are available to motivate subject movement in Icelandic. They demonstrate that [case] is an attracting feature in at least two languages, Irish and Icelandic. Hence they argue that minimalist theory requires the dissociation of morphological and structural case, and that Icelandic Transitive Expletive Constructions require neither an unforced violation of Procrastinate, nor distinction between deletion and erasure. They conclude that if the notion of 'strong' feature is to be preserved, Minimalism must allow both non- categorial attracting features and Case-features which play an active role in the computational component oF(some) human language. They claim that EPP is not uniformly realized across all languages, but varies according to which feature (s) may be strong.

    A paper which should motivate similar studies in other languages.

    2) Null Subjects in Hungarian DPs AND Inflected Infinitivals, by Anik� Csirmaz Hungarian possessive constructions and inflected infinitivals allow a pro subject with no apparent Case- checker. Splitting Case-checking between specifier and head on the one hand, and via an Agr projection on the other, it is argued that pro is a full pronominal. If the lexical head cannot check its Case feature, pro will behave like an element with a Case value [null] visible for LF processes, but not interpretable at PF. The Numeration may also include an Agr; it will check the [nominative] specification of the pronoun, rendering it visible at PF as well. The Case-checking mechanism evades optionality in derivation-different strings are derived from different outputs.

    3) That-t Effects in English and Yiddish, by Kerstin Hoge The paper presents an attempt at reanalysing that-t(race) effect in accordance with minimalist principles. It is argued that that-t effect results from a violation of the Access Constraint which requires checking of a [+Int] feature to occur at either two adjacent functional heads or at two heads of the same category.

    Extraction out of finite clauses in English shows a clear subj(ect) - obj(ect) asymmetry which is commonly termed 'that-t effect'. While a subject cannot be extracted across an overt complementiser, object extraction is grammatical, irrespective of whether there is an overt complementiser or not.

    The that-t effect, originally accounted for by Chomsky & Lasnik's that- t filter (1977: 451, (65) ), is standardly explained as an ECP violation.

    Notwithstanding the various developments of ECP in the literature, two ideas have remained central in the analysis of that-t effect:

    i) that-t effect results from the failure of government; ii) lexical C is non-transparent, whereas a non-lexical C can be coindexed with an intermediate trace in Spec CP.

    This raises the Question: How can that-t effect be accounted for in the minimalist framework, which has abandoned government as a basic syntactic notion? One might explore the idea that since ECP violations are not a uniform phenomenon, that-t effect is "due to something else entirely" (Culicover 1997: 261). Hence the proposal is: 'That-t effect results from a violation of the Access Constraint -- i.e., Multiple access of +Int features must occur in a head-head relation'.

    Access Constraint: Where F is [+int] and X and Y are not of the same category, if F is accessed by X and Y, Xmax and Y must be sisters.

    On the assumption that the wh-feature is a variant of [D], this approach singles out subjects, since subject but not object wh-phrases must check their categorial feature against I(nfl). The Access Constraint is further shown to give an account of the adverb effect, provided that embedded topicalisation in English involves CP-recursion.

    Yiddish not only exhibits the that-t effect, but also bans object extraction in the absence of an overt complementiser. The fact that wh- movement out of complementiser-less clauses must proceed through the lower Spec CP position is attributed to Shortest Move. Finally, the fact that subject extraction across an overt complementiser is possible in non-subject-initial clauses is linked to the phenomenon of null subjects. Embedded topicalisation in Yiddish is argued to constitute IP-adjunction with Spec IP being occupied by a null expletive.

    4) Evidence for Focus Features, by Virginia Motapanyane The empirical evidence presented in this paper points to a correlation between fronting to Focus and properties of T in Romanian. That is, fronting to Focus is allowed only when the D-feature of T is checked in TP. This observation matches the existing arguments in the literature for a correlation between [wh] and [Focus]. The ensuing hypothesis is that [focus] occurs in Syntax only in conjunction with some label feature, such as [tense] and [wh], which are semantically related. Association between [focus] and [wh]/[tense] takes place in the lexicon, so that complex [focus+wh] or [focus+tense] features enter the Numeration and merge in C and T respectively. Hence a typology of fronting to Focus follows, contrasting English with fronting to Focus through clefts or topicalization, and Romanian, with fronting to Focus to Spec TP. This typology extends of interrogative clauses, since wh- mov(ement) implies movement to a Focus position. Important cross linguistic variation in these structures follow naturally from the treatment of fronting to Focus as a checking operation against the functional heads specified for [focus+wh] or [focus+tense].

    Romanian data shows that fronting to focus places the constituent between the subject and the inflected verb, in both declarative and interrogative clauses. Any constituent may front to this preverbal position and receive the specific focal stress. Nominal phrases contrast w. r. t. the type of chains they head from pre-verbal focus -- a definite DP participates in clitic pronoun chains whereas indefinites and QPs form operator variable chains. The same strategy for fronting to Focus appears in complement clauses. In sum, Romanian fronting to focus targets a TP position, triggers alternate chain types, and cannot overlap with wh-move. This contrasts with English, where, fronting to focus, through clefts and topicalization, targets a position outside TP, forms operator-variable chains only and co-occurs with wh-move.

    The analysis of preverbal focus in Romanian is based on the assumption that focus features are specified on T, along with other inflectional features. The tests show that fronting to Focus is correlated with the D-feature on T: only the clauses in which [D] is checked against DP/NP argument allow for fronting to Focus within TP.

    The option [focus+wh] is not available to Romanian because this language lacks the quantificational context that is necessary for derivations with fronting to Focus within CP. For Romanian, the association [focus+wh] leads to illicit derivations in the language. Particularly, the way in which it is instantiated -- through dissociated landing sites for [wh] and [focus] checking -- it brings further support to the syntactic correlation between wh- and focus movement.

    An interesting paper, which brings forth dimensions of Focus hitherto unnoticed in the literature.

    5) [Q] Checking IN Mandarin Chinese Yes-No Questions, by Ning Zhang Being a data oriented paper, its empirical contribution is significant, and will benefit researchers interested in the parametric study of question types. The author systematically identifies the yes-no question types in Chinese, studies their syntactic properties, and then presents an unified treatment to these five types of yes-no questions, and explores further the conditions under which a choice is made between overt and covert checking.

    For example, in Chinese, (a C-final language), a yes-no question can be asked in one of five ways: S-ma, S-not-V, S-not, A-not-A, and shi-bu- shi.

    i) S-ma questions are formed by attaching a complementizer 'ma' at the end of a declarative sentence. ii) S-not-V questions are formed by attaching the word 'bu'"not" or 'mei' "not" plus a copy of the matrix verb at the end of a declarative sentence. iii) S-not questions are formed by attaching a word 'bu' "not" or 'mei'"not" at the end of a declarative sentence. iv) A-not-A questions are formed by reduplication of the first syllable or the complete form of the questioned element and an infixation of 'bu' or 'mei' between the reduplicant and the base. a) A-bu-A occurs with unbounded eventualities. b) A-mei-A occurs with bounded eventualities. c) The element 'A' in A-not-A can be a preposition, an adjective, as well as a verb. v) 'Shi' can be a contrastive focus marker in Chinese.

    The syntactic relationship among these five types of Chinese yes-no questions is studied. It is found that S-not type shares many syntactic properties with S-not-V type and may be a PF variant of S-not-V.

    It is claimed that a strong [Q] of C is overtly checked by a merge 'ma' in S-ma questions and by sigma -to-C raising in S-not- (V) questions, where sigma is a general functional head, where both sentential [Neg] and other propositional features can be hosted. Chinese sigma can be either interrogative or negative, and interrogative sigma has two strong features: [Q] and [V]. They are checked by the word 'bu' or 'mei (you) and a copy of the verb respectively. Thus, Chinese yes-no questions can have 'not-V-support', which is similar to do-support in English matrix yes-no questions, which explains the presence of not-V in S-not-V questions. Hence, sigma -to-C raising in S-not- (V) questions adjoins the word bu/mei (you) and the copy of the verb to C. In addition, A-not-A and shi-bu-shi questions check the [-int][Q] of C by covert movement. Thus in these various yes-no questions, checking may be both overt and covert and can take the form of both Merge and Move operations. Furthermore, the interactions between a yes-no question and a sentence negation exhibit Relativized Minimality and feature compatibility. Finally, the theoretical relations among these checking operations is explored.

    Section IV: Ellipsis, Reconstruction and Related Phenomenon 1) A Minimalist Theory of LF Copy, by Satoshi Oku The author claims in this paper that sloppy identity is not symmetrical but is allowed only in one direction, and that this asymmetry receives a natural account under an LF copy approach to VP-Ellipsis. Following a long tradition of interpretive approaches to VP-Ellipsis, it is assumed that what licenses VP-Ellipsis is the LF operation which copies features of the antecedent. Hence, it follows that the reconstructed site cannot have more features than the original antecedent has. A question to ask then is whether copying of features 'fewer than' the original is possible.

    The concept of Move-F(eature) in Chomsky (1995) makes it explicit that relevant features of a lexical item can be affected by LF syntactic operations. In other words, 'LF feature decomposition' of a lexical item is possible. The author extends the idea of LF feature decomposition to the LF Copy operation in ellipsis structures, proposing that: The LF Copy operation allows copying of a subset of the original features of an antecedent onto the ellipsis site. That is, the features of the reconstructed elliptic site can be (to some extent) fewer than the features of its antecedent source, while they cannot be more than the features of the antecedent.

    Based on data from English, the proposed analysis gives a unified account of seemingly unrelated facts observed in VP-Ellipsis:

    i) sloppy identity of verbal morphology between the antecedent verb and the elliptic verb is possible only when the verbal morphology feature in the elliptic site is a subset of the verbal morphology of the antecedent VP, but not vice versa.

    ii) an R-expression and a reflexive in the antecedent VP can be the reconstruction source of the corresponding pronoun in the elliptic site, but a pronoun in the antecedent VP cannot be the reconstruction source of the corresponding reflexive.

    ii) follows, given the natural assumption that the features composing a pronoun are a subset of the features composing the corresponding R- expression, or of the features composing the corresponding reflexive in English.

    The author points out that an interesting further project would be to make a thorough comparison of the present LF copy approach and another traditional approach to VP-Ellipsis, the (PF) -Deletion approach.

    2) A/A-Bar Movement and Attract-F, by Juan Romero-Morales and Norberto Moreno-Quib�n It has been observed that A-movement and A-bar movement behave differently with respect to reconstruction effects. Only arguments moved to A-bar positions are able to reconstruct. By contrast, arguments moved to A-positions do not reconstruct. This asymmetry between A/A-bar movement does not follow from any principle of grammar. Moreover, it goes against the spirit of the Minimalist program, since it assumes that there are two types of movement subject to different constraints.

    The authors propose that this asymmetry can be derived from the properties of the rule Attract-F. Chomsky (1995: 297) argues that movement must be understood as attraction of formal features.

    1) K attracts F if F is the closest feature that can enter into a checking relation with a sublabel of K.

    The fact that apparently the whole category is moving is due to the properties of the morphophonological component to ensure convergence at this level, and need not be stipulated in the formulation of Attract F. If this is the case, only the feature attracted moves at LF. The proposal therefore is that the A/A-bar movement asymmetry can be established out of this property in terms of 2).

    2a) Attracted features cannot be reconstructed; 2b) Pied-piped features must be reconstructed.

    It is argued that 2) is all that is needed to explain the existence of different types of movement. This demands that the features attracted in A-movement and the features attracted in A-bar movement are different. The proposal is that formal features are organized under different sublabels. One sublabel includes operator-like features involved in processes like wh-movement, topicalization, etc., the other sublabel includes the features involved in A-movement(categorial features, Case, and phi-features). Only features dominated by the sublabel that contains the feature attracted are carried along as 'free-riders' and form a derivative chain. If this is correct, the apparent lack of reconstruction effects in instances of A-movement may be attributed to the fact that the attracted features are precisely those that encode referentiality (Chomsky 1995).

    In order to give an account of the differences traditionally attributed to the distinction between A/A-bar movement, the notion of Extended Domain is introduced. Specifically, the proposal is that when an element raises, it extends its binding domain up to its landing position. It is also shown that the notion of extended domain and the generalization in 2) offer a straight forward explanation of Backward Binding facts, which have not received a satisfactory account in literature.

    Section V: DPs: Features and Syntactic Relations 1) Object Agreement in Hungarian: A Case for Minimalism, by Huba Bartos This paper investigates the syntactic aspects of object agreement in Hungarian. Hungarian displays two verbal agreement paradigms 'subjective conjugation' and 'objective conjugation' respectively. In very general terms, verbs used intransitively are invariably affixed with the subjective inflectional endings, while with transitively used verbs the choice between the paradigms depends on some property of the object. Roughly speaking, if the object is a definite NP, it goes with 'objective' agreement on the verb, whereas if it is indefinite, the 'subjective' paradigm is chosen. When there is no object, the choice defaults to the subjective inflection. However, when the object includes a possessive construction, the verb usually appears with the objective paradigm, even though the same indefinite determiner is present(and accordingly, the NP is still interpreted as indefinite. ) In such cases, the verb could carry subjective endings too, but with a different(non-specific) interpretation. A similar pattern is shown with an indefinite pronoun. Surprisingly, the determiner 'minden' "every", which is usually cited as a typical definite determiner, normally triggers subjective agreement. The presence of a possessive construction however results in a switch to object agreement. Likewise, if 'minden' is preceded by the definite article, the object pattern appears.

    On the basis of more such examples, it is concluded that neither the definiteness itself, nor the possessive construction (possibly seen as giving rise to definiteness), on its own, can be used as an explanation for the distribution of object agreement.

    Again, there is a sharp contrast between 3rd person pronouns and 1st/2nd person pronouns. When objects, the former trigger objective agreement, the latter on the other hand require subjective agreement. Adopting the phrase structure attributed to Hungarian nominal phrases presented in Szabolcsi (1992, 1994) the author shows that: "V bears objective inflection iff it has a DP as its object."

    At the heart of the suggestion lies the assumption that nominal phrases are not uniform categorially; some project a DP layer and while others do not, and this entails important differences in their behaviour. Specifically, the account capitalizes on the minimalist view of Case- licensing, according to which Case is a feature of D0, whereby nominal phrases not projecting a DP layer will not participate in any case licensing mechanism, thus they will not be visible objects for the verb in the process of case checking.

    The author argues on the basis of the analysis presented, that the minimalist framework is superior to its predecessor Government and Binding theory in its ability to capture the facts involved. Both empirically and theoretically finer aspects of Nominal constructions are brought out.

    2) Demonstratives in a Feature-Based Theory of Syntax, by Luis Silva- Villar and Javier Guti�rrez-Rexach In this paper, a fully derivational and feature-based analysis of demonstrative DPs in Spanish is presented. Special attention is paid to the diachronic origin of Spanish demonstratives and to the features of this class of lexical resources that are [+Interpretable] at the LF interface. In general, the paper provides evidence for the claim that a minimalist perspective allows for a deeper understanding of the relationships between synchronic and diachronic morphology, and between syntactic features and semantic interpretation.

    The behaviour of Spanish demonstratives support the idea that the grammar of demonstrative DPs cannot be derived from the grammar of definite DPs. The expressions headed by demonstratives behave differently from those headed by definite and existential determiners. If demonstratives have a particular set of interpretable features which are different from the set of features of articles and existentials, then it follows from minimalist assumptions that their behavior in the computational system will be different.

    The authors take as a point of departure the Old Spanish productive form 'aquel' as the most representative element of the system that gives us a definite clue to the understanding of the derivational history of demonstratives in general. The lexical item 'aquel' is a complex word that carries a number of features that must be checked to avoid a crash of the derivation. It is composed of:

    a) ECCE---a type of emphatic deictic form b) EUM -- an anaphoric demonstrative pronoun c) ILLE -- a demonstrative

    Because of that, the original meaning of 'aquel' is close to 'here he is'/'here the +Noun is'. Such deictic derivations are analyzed in Silva-Villar (1996) as instances of derivations headed by deictic units generated in C in which the nominal features of T(Chomsky 1992) have been incorporated into C. In accordance with Chomsky, T contains both a feature for the licensing of a DP (a D-feature) and a feature for the licensing of a verb (V-feature). Neither D nor V features are interpretable at the interface levels, which forces them to be eliminated by checking operations at Spell-out. The final configuration, D/N (of T) -to-C, spells out a complex C. This analysis is adopted here.

    The empirical results are based on the interaction of features never considered in previous studies, such as double demonstratives and Topic demonstratives, among others. Additionally, it is shown that there are some strong dependencies between demonstratives and a specific series of adjectives and weak quantifiers as licensers. The outcome is not predicted by any previous theory of DP but is easily accomodated in the present work.

    CRITICAL EVALUATION Despite later developments in the Minimalist Program Chomsky (1998, 1999, 2001, etc.), the papers in this volume are very important with regard not only to the issues that they address and the analyses they provide, but also to their empirical content. Though most of the papers are very elaborate theoretically, giving a lot of weight to the historical aspect of the theory, and then explaining why a modification is necessary, some are entirely data oriented, and bring out finer points either unnoticed before, or rarely taken note of in the literature. What is lacking however, is a comprehensive introduction by the editors themselves. Small notes in the beginning of each Section, explaining the logic of such a division could also have helped. There are some typos, which I have chosen to ignore. All said and done, this an enlightening book, which however makes a lot of demands on the reader.

    REFERENCES Bobaljik, Jonathan David (2001). A-chains at the PF-interface: Copies and "covert" movement. Natural Language and Linguistic Theory.

    Chomsky, N. 1965. Aspects of the theory of syntax. Cambridge, Mass. : MIT Press.

    Chomsky, N. 1981. Lectures on government and binding. Dordrecht: Foris.

    Chomsky, N. 1986a. Barriers. Cambridge, Mass. : MIT Press.

    Chomsky, N. 1986b. Knowledge of language. New York; Praeger.

    Chomsky, N. 1992. "A Minimalist Program for Linguistic Theory" (MIT Occasional Papers in Linguistics, 1). Cambridge, Mass: MIT. [Repr. As Chap 3 of Chomsky 1995: 167-218]

    Chomsky, N. 1994. Bare phrase structure.

    Chomsky, N. 1995. The Minimalist Program. Cambridge, MIT press .

    Chomsky, N. 1998. Minimalist Inquiries: The Framework. MIT Occasional Papers in Linguistics No. 15. MITWPL.

    Chomsky, N. 1999. Derivation By Phase. MIT Occasional Papers in Linguistics No. 18. MITWPL

    Chomsky, Noam. 2001. 'Beyond Explanatory Adequacy' Ms. MIT

    Chomsky, Noam & Howard Lasnik 1977. "Filters and Control". LI 8. 425- 504.

    Chomsky, Noam, and Howard Lasnik. 1993. The theory of principles and parameters. In J. Jacobs, A. von Stechow, W. Sternefeld, and T. Vennemann, eds., Syntax: An international handbook of contemporary research. Berlin: de Gruyter.

    Culicover, Peter. 1997. Principles and Parameters. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Grimshaw, Jane. 1991. Extended projection. Ms., Brandeis University, Waltham, Mass.

    Hornstein, Norbert. 1995. Logical Form, from GB to Minimalism. Oxford & Cambridge, Mass: Basil Blackwell.

    Kayne, Richard 1994. The Antisymmetry of Syntax. Cambridge, Mass: MIT press.

    Marantz, Alec. 1984. On the Nature of Grammatical Relations. Cambridge, Mass: MIT press.

    Rizzi, Luigi. 1991. Residual Verb Second and the Wh Criterion (=Technical Reports in Formal and Computational Linguistics, 3). University of Geneva, Geneva.

    Silva-Villar, Luis. 1996. Enclisis in Northwestern Iberian Languages: A diachronic theory. PhD dissertation, University of California, Los Angeles.

    Speas, Margaret. 1986. Adjunctions and Projections in Syntax. Ph. D. dissertation, MIT, Cambridge, Mass.

    Szabolcsi, Anna (1992) : "Subordination Articles and Complementizers". Approaches to Hungarian, vol IV, ed., by Istv�n Kenesei, 123-137. Szeged: JATE.

    Szabolcsi, Anna. 1994. All quantifiers are not equal: the case of focus. appeared in Acta Linguistica Hungarica.

    Szabolcsi Anna (1995) : On Modes of Operation . Forum talk at the Tenth Amsterdam Colloquium in Language, Logic and Information (1995) ; appeared in the proceedings

    Ura, H. 1996. Multiple Feature Checking: A Theory of Grammatical Function Splitting. PhD dissertation, MIT, Cambridge, Mass.

    ABOUT THE REVIEWER: I submitted my PhD thesis at the University of Hyderabad, India, in March 2001. I am STILL awaiting my viva !!! My research interests include Minimalist Syntax (morphology included), Semantics, and their application in Computational Syntax and Semantics. I am presently working on my book on 'Bangla Syntax' and on a paper on 'Object Shift'.

    It is my constant endeavour to bring to people's notice that linguistic literature SHOULD be easily available in India, if not in libraries, through INTERNET or in book stores, at a reasonable price, and in INDIAN CURRENCY, just as journals and books of ALL OTHER SUBJECTS (viz., Physics, Medicine, Anthropology etc.) are available, so that one doesn't have to give up Linguistics for want of a job or for want of literature -- which is often the case, unfortunately.