LINGUIST List 13.372

Mon Feb 11 2002

Review: Legendre, Grimshaw & Vikner, OT Syntax

Editor for this issue: Terence Langendoen <terrylinguistlist.org>


What follows is another discussion note contributed to our Book Discussion Forum. We expect these discussions to be informal and interactive; and the author of the book discussed is cordially invited to join in.

If you are interested in leading a book discussion, look for books announced on LINGUIST as "available for discussion." (This means that the publisher has sent us a review copy.) Then contact Simin Karimi at siminlinguistlist.org or Terry Langendoen at terrylinguistlist.org.

Subscribe to Blackwell's LL+ at http://www.linguistlistplus.com/ and donate 20% of your subscription to LINGUIST! You get 30% off on Blackwells books, and free shipping and postage!


Directory

  • Alex Alsina, review of Legendre et al., Optimality-Theoretic Syntax

    Message 1: review of Legendre et al., Optimality-Theoretic Syntax

    Date: Mon, 11 Feb 2002 09:36:34 +0100
    From: Alex Alsina <alex.alsinatrad.upf.es>
    Subject: review of Legendre et al., Optimality-Theoretic Syntax


    Legendre, G�raldine, Jane Grimshaw, and Sten Vikner, ed. (2001) Optimality-Theoretic Syntax. MIT Press, xviii+548pp, paperback ISBN 0-262-62138-X, $42.00, A Bradford Book.

    Alex Alsina, Universitat Pompeu Fabra.

    Optimality-Theoretic Syntax is an edited collection of papers that share the feature of applying the framework and ideas of Optimality Theory (OT) to the domain of syntax. An overview by the editors highlighting the main contributions of each paper precedes the body of the book, consisting of sixteen chapters. In what follows I first give a brief summary of each paper, in the order in which they appear in the book, and then make general remarks about the versions of OT that are presented in this volume.

    SUMMARY G�raldine Legendre, An Introduction to Optimality Theory in Syntax, presents an overview of OT as it applies to syntax with the purpose of making the rest of the volume accessible to a reader who is not familiar with OT. This chapter illustrates the main ideas of this formal theory of constraint interaction by means of analyses of various syntactic phenomena. And points out the similarity between syntax and phonology, since, within OT, "the two modules operate on the basis of the same formal and markedness principles."

    Peter Ackema and Ad Neeleman, Competition between Syntax and Phonology, account for the observation that certain complex lexical items (such as verb-particle complexes in Dutch) can alternate between a morphological realization and a syntactic realization depending on the environment. Assuming that such complex expressions are generated either in the morphology or in the syntax, the choice between these two modules will be the result of the application of constraints (one favoring syntactic structures over morphological structures and one requiring affixes to select morphological hosts).

    Judith Aissen, Markedness and Subject Choice in Optimality Theory, accounts for the presence and use of morphology signaling marked subject choice (ergative case, inverse, passive, etc.) crosslinguistically. The analysis makes crucial use of the formal devices of harmonic alignment of prominence scales and local conjunction and of the claim that there are scales of person and animacy, semantic role, and grammatical relations underlying the association between these types of information.

    Eric Bakovic and Edward Keer, Optionality and Ineffability, propose an analysis of the distribution of complementizers in English and Norwegian, accounting for when the complementizer is obligatorily present or absent and when optional. Optionality in this case results from different inputs and consequently different candidate sets with the relevant faithfulness constraints outranking markedness, whereas the obligatory situations result from a ranking of the relevant markedness constraint above faithfulness, which has the effect of neutralizing differences in the inputs.

    Joan Bresnan, The Emergence of the Unmarked Pronoun, proposes constraints relating the form of personal pronouns (zero, bound, clitic, weak, or pronoun) with the properties of pronouns (anaphoricity, topic-anaphoricity, and classification by agreement features) in order to explain certain crosslinguistic generalizations. These include the claim that languages may lack bound or zero pronouns, but no language lacks free forms, and that, in languages where bound and free pronominals coexist, the free pronoun is used for focus where a bound form is available, but has a nonfocus use only when the bound form is lacking.

    Hye-Won Choi, Binding and Discourse Prominence: Reconstruction in "Focus" Scrambling, analyses the binding and focality facts associated with scrambling in German as a result of constraint competition between two components of grammar, syntax and discourse. The scrambling facts follow from the interaction of a syntactic constraint, requiring subjects to precede nonsubjects, with two discourse constraints, requiring old and prominent information to precede new and nonprominent information respectively, and the binding facts are explained by a local conjunction of constraints in operator binding requiring the binder to linearly precede its bindee and to outrank it in the functional hierarchy.

    Jo�o Costa, The Emergence of Unmarked Word Order, explains the unmarked word orders in different languages through the reranking of a small set of constraints. These constraints are a combination of purely syntactic constraints (such as the requirement that the subject be in SpecIP or a constraint penalizing movement) and of constraints that take into account discourse information such as focus and topic. The languages that illustrate the various rankings of constraints include Portuguese, Spanish (two dialects), Italian, Greek, Arabic, Berber, Chamorro, Malagasy, and Celtic.

    Jane Grimshaw, Optimal Clitic Positions and the Lexicon in Romance Clitic Systems, accounts for the order of clitics in combination, some restrictions on clitic combinations, and the actual inventory of clitic specifications in several Romance languages. The order of clitics follows from a set of positional constraints that are satisfied when an element with the relevant specification is placed at the designated edge of the cluster. The selection of unexpected clitics in combination such as Spanish "spurious se" follows from ranking certain positional constraints above faithfulness constraints. Finally, the ranking of constraints predicts the set of morphosyntactic combinations that can be found in a clitic system.

    G�raldine Legendre, Masked Second-position Effects and the Linearization of Functional Features, proposes a unified analysis of verb-second phenomena (such as is found the Germanic languages) and second position clitics (as in many South Slavic languages). The claim is that finite verbs and clitics are linearized at Phonetic Form (PF) by two conflicting constraints, one requiring the relevant feature not to be realized in intonational phrase-initial position and another one requiring this feature to be left-aligned with the edge of the nearest projection of the head that this feature is associated with. If the former constraint outranks the latter, the relevant element appears in second position; if the latter outranks the former, the relevant element appears in initial position.

    Gereon M�ller, Order Preservation, Parallel Movement, and the Emergence of the Unmarked, proposes a constraint that requires c-command relations to be preserved across levels of syntactic representation, which interacts with constraints favoring movement as well as with a constraint penalizing movement. The newly proposed constraint accounts for situations in which the D-structure order of constituents is preserved at S-structure, including superiority effects in English, wh-movement in Bulgarian, pronominal object shift in Danish, object shift of lexical NPs in Icelandic, Case-driven NP raising, pronoun fronting in German, and relative scope and QR in German.

    Vieri Samek-Lodovici, Crosslinguistic Typologies in Optimality Theory, investigates the structure of the typology entailed by any language-specific analysis within OT. The formal properties of OT typologies are illustrated through the analysis of the syntax of new-information focus. The basic word order of a language and other facts are claimed to emerge as epiphenomenal effects of constraints governing phrase-structure and movement and constraints governing the syntactic realization of focused phrases.

    Peter Sells, Form and Function in the Typology of Grammatical Voice Systems, proposes to derive the inventory of voice forms in any language from the language-particular ranking of constraints. Different inventories of voice forms are evaluated relative to each other and the winning candidate is the actual voice system of the language. The analysis involves the assumption that arguments have three levels of prominence, that these levels of prominence constrain the linking to grammatical functions, and that thematic roles also constrain the linking to grammatical functions. The unmarked linking is the best candidate in an OT evaluation and is claimed to be the morphologically unmarked form in the language; the next most optimal candidate with contrasting prominence relations will be a morphologically marked voice form, if the language has one contrast; and so on if the language has more than one contrast.

    Margaret Speas, Constraints on Null Pronouns, proposes a set of violable constraints, which, variously ranked, give the facts of English, where null pronouns occur only in the subject position of nonfinite clauses, the facts of Thai, where null pronouns occur as subjects and objects regardless of finiteness, and the facts of Spanish, where null pronouns occur only as subjects regardless of finiteness. She also brings out the importance of the role of point of view in the licensing and interpretation of null pronouns.

    Sten Vikner, V-to-I movement and do-Insertion in Optimality Theory, deals with the position of the finite verb relative to a sentential adverb and to negation, the occurrence of auxiliary do, and the optionality or obligatoriness of complementizers in English, Danish, French, and Icelandic. These facts, both within a language and across languages, are derived from an interacting set of constraints that are ranked differently in each language. An interesting empirical claim is the idea that the obligatoriness or optionality of complementizers in a given language correlates with apparently unrelated properties of the language such as the position of the finite verb.

    Colin Wilson, Bidirectional Optimization and the Theory of Anaphora, motivates two types of competition on the basis of binding phenomena: interpretive competition, where competing sentences differ in their semantic interpretation but not in their syntactic structure, and expressive competition, where candidates have the same intended meaning but differ in their syntactic structure. Data revealing a variable binding domain for certain anaphors motivate the first type of competition, and the partial complementarity of pronouns and anaphors in some languages motivates the latter. The paper proposes to integrate both types of competition in a bidirectional model of the syntax-semantics interface.

    Ellen Woolford, Case Patterns, accounts for situations in which there is a potential competition among Cases by having markedness constraints that require avoidance of marked Cases interacting with faithfulness constraints that require the presence of lexically determined Case features. The data accounted for include structures in which the presence of a particular Case depends on the presence of another Case, such as structures in which an accusative argument is only possible if there is another nominative argument, structures in which a particular Case is only possible with certain aspectual features, as with ergative Case and perfective aspect in Hindi, among others.

    GENERAL REMARKS The application of Optimality Theory to syntactic analysis has a shorter history than the application of Optimality Theory to theories of phonology, but, by now, OT has established a solid foothold in syntactic analysis and this volume is definite proof of this. OT represents an important change in the way we think about linguistic theory and analysis. Among other differences with non-OT analyses, checking the predictions of a theory that involves OT is no longer a matter of determining whether a given structure violates the principles (or, rather, constraints) of a theory, since a given structure may violate some constraints and yet be well-formed. Such a structure is grammatical if there is no other structure among those it competes with that has fewer violations of the most highly ranked constraint on which the two structures differ. Thus, the grammaticality of a structure does not involve only the structure in question and the set of principles or constraints of the theory, but crucially the whole (infinite) set of competing structures. This makes checking the predictions of the theory potentially very complicated (which may be a problem from the point of view of a reader who wants to evaluate a theory, but is not necessarily a defect of the theory or a drawback from the point of view of the linguist proposing the theory). In any case, it becomes very important to establish the set of competitors, or candidate set, out of which a grammatical structure has to emerge. The set of competitors is characterized by a common input. And what the input is in syntax emerges from the collection of papers in Optimality-Theoretic Syntax as one of the unresolved problems facing the application of OT to syntax: there is no consensus among the OT syntacticians represented in this volume as to how the input is defined and, consequently, as to how the candidate set is defined. What follows concerns this important issue.

    In OT applied to phonology, the input is taken to consist of lexical contrasts (underlying representations). The set of principles called GEN applies to any input producing a large number of structures that constitute the candidate set. The ranked constraints in EVAL pick out the optimal candidate as the grammatical structure. This model of grammar is perfectly consistent with the standard conception that there is a division in grammar between general statements and item-specific statements. The former kind of statement is expressed as rules, principles, constraints, etc. that apply to large classes of structures, whereas the latter kind is information about a particular linguistic item, be it a word, a morpheme, a syntactic structure, etc. This suggests that there are two broad components in grammar reflecting this distinction: the component of regularities, containing all the general properties, and the lexical component, containing all the item-specific properties. OT phonology adopts this view: the lexical component provides the input and the component of regularities is divided into two subcomponents: the subcomponent that generates structures for the inputs-GEN, which consists of inviolable constraints-and the subcomponent that contains statements that are sufficiently general and recurrent crosslinguistically to merit being considered regularities, but may fail to be satisfied in particular linguistic expressions-EVAL, which consists of violable constraints.

    One could imagine that this overall model might also be applied to syntax. The input would consist of lexical items, or, more precisely, the syntactic information of lexical items, if we are only concerned with syntax, which would include categorial information, argument structure, agreement features, case features, etc. GEN would take this input, build structures for it, manipulate it in various ways by adding or deleting features, etc. and generate an infinite number of candidates for EVAL. This simple (or, perhaps, simple-minded) extension of OT to syntax is seldom what we find in actual syntactic analyses that use OT. Most, if not all, of the papers in this volume adopt a more elaborate view in which the input does not consist only of lexical items, that is, item-specific or idiosyncratic information. Furthermore, there is considerable discrepancy among the authors as to what else, in addition to lexical information, is part of the input. Some discussion about the nature of the input in syntax can be found in some of the chapters, such as Speas's, pp. 399-400.

    Whatever the reasons may be for rejecting the idea that the input contains nothing but lexical information, the fact is that it has some important consequences. In the first place, it breaks the parallel between phonology and syntax that is often presented as a positive feature of the extension of OT to syntax (as in Legendre's introductory chapter in this volume). Whereas the input in phonology consists only of lexical information, that would not be the case with the input in syntax. In the second place, allowing more than just lexical information in the input implicitly introduces a third subcomponent within the system of regularities, in addition to GEN and EVAL. If the input contains structure, features, specifications, etc., beyond what is provided by the lexical component, it means that some set of rules has added this non-lexical information. The existence of this "pre-input" set of rules is not explicitly acknowledged by any of the authors in this volume. In the third place, since this "pre-input" set of rules is not even mentioned, there is no discussion about what it is, what it does, or how it does what it does, which means that there is a portion of the theory that needs to be clarified. In the fourth place, and closely related to the latter two points, there is a considerable amount of variation among authors about what the input is. For some authors the input has very little more than the bare lexical information (this would seem to be the case with M�ller's proposal in Optimality-Theoretic Syntax); for other authors the input consists of full-fledged syntactic structures (which seems to be the proposal in Wilson's chapter). It is perfectly legitimate for different authors to have different theoretical conceptions. But, as long as there is no unified view about what the input is in OT syntax, the term "OT" will simply denote a formal framework of constraint interaction. One might expect "OT" also to denote a model of grammar specifying what the various components or subcomponents of the grammar are (e.g., a lexical component and one or more components of regularities) and how they interact. As it is, there is no general consensus about OT as a model of grammar in the sense intended here.

    To try to make this last point clearer, if OT is no more than a formal framework of constraint interaction, as described in Legendre's chapter, page 3, there is no restriction on what an input can be. Within this view, a linguist interested in explaining a certain phenomenon has to define an input so that a candidate set can be generated by GEN and subsequently evaluated by EVAL, but the input can be anything to which linguistic principles and constraints can apply, ranging from sets of morphosyntactic features to full-fledged syntactic structures. Depending on what phenomenon the linguist is interested in explaining, the nature of the input will be defined in one way or another. For phenomenon A, the input would be defined using one set of criteria, whereas, for phenomenon B, it would be defined using a different set of criteria. This situation seems undesirable because there is no substance attached to the term "input": it is just a concept in the formal framework of constraint interaction known as OT. I expect that linguists working within OT will eventually converge on a model of grammar for OT, in which concepts such as "input" will have a commonly accepted definition in substantive terms.

    To conclude, Optimality-Theoretic Syntax is an excellently edited volume, containing sixteen papers that present interesting analyses of a variety of syntactic phenomena. The fact that the papers taken as a whole reveal what seems to me to be a problem for a unified conception of OT as a model of grammar in the sense indicated earlier does not detract from the high quality of the volume or of the individual papers. I believe this volume is essential for anyone interested in the application of OT to the syntactic domain or, more generally, in syntactic theory.

    BIOGRAPHICAL SKETCH I received my PhD from Stanford University in 1993. My research interests are argument structure, complex predicates, object asymmetries and, more generally, linguistic theory.