LINGUIST List 14.1691

Mon Jun 16 2003

Review: Linguistic Theories: Alexiadou, ed. (2002)

Editor for this issue: Naomi Ogasawara <naomilinguistlist.org>


What follows is a review or discussion note contributed to our Book Discussion Forum. We expect discussions to be informal and interactive; and the author of the book discussed is cordially invited to join in.

If you are interested in leading a book discussion, look for books announced on LINGUIST as "available for review." Then contact Simin Karimi at siminlinguistlist.org.


Directory

  • Sergei Sey, Theoretical Approaches to Universals

    Message 1: Theoretical Approaches to Universals

    Date: Sat, 14 Jun 2003 16:45:54 +0000
    From: Sergei Sey <rusakovAR2015.spb.edu>
    Subject: Theoretical Approaches to Universals


    Alexiadou, Artemis, ed. (2002) Theoretical Approaches to Universals, John Benjamins Publishing Company, Linguistik Aktuell/Linguistics Today 49.

    Announced at http://linguistlist.org/issues/13/13-2678.html

    Sergey Say, ILI RAN (Institute for linguistic research of the Russian Academy of Sciences), Saint-Petersburg, Russia

    This volume presents a selection of papers from the GLOW conference on universals organized by the Research Center for General Linguistics (Berlin), the Linguistic Department of the University of Potsdam and the Dutch Graduate School in Linguistics (Berlin, March 1999). The authors of the contributions to the volume all share a generativist (in most cases, a minimalist) background; the goal of the volume is to enrich our knowledge of what is universal and what is language- specific in linguistic structures, and in particular to answer some of the following questions: ''how are the primitive notions of the structure building apparatus, Merge, Move, Agree or Attract defined? (...) What does a typology of features look like? (...) [H]ow are we to understand variation in morpho- lexical features exactly? Finally, is it true that morphological variation dispenses with the need for structural variation?'' (p. 5).

    SUMMARY

    The book opens with an introduction by the volume's editor, Artemis Alexiadou. This introduction is itself divided into two parts, the first containing a brief overview of the current state of affairs in the universals research (with special emphasis on convergences and discrepancies between generative and functional-typological approach), the second giving a summary of the contributions to the volume. The rest of the volume consists of 9 papers and a subject index (with an in-built language index). References are given after each paper.

    The first paper of the book (''Universal features and language- particular morphemes'', by Maya Arad) elaborates on the well-known view that assigns variation among languages to morphology (Chomsky 1995). A specific formulation of this view is offered, namely, that ''there are three sources for language variation: the inventory of roots a language has, the features it has selected out of a universal inventory, and the way these features are bundled together'' (p. 15). In particular, Arad investigates those features that are bundled together in the upper head in the VP- shell; this head (commonly referred to as ''little v'') introduces an external argument in its specifier and enters into a relation with the object. Arad observes semantic and syntactic properties of verbs denoting mental states (psych verbs) in a number of languages (Italian and other Romance first of all); she distinguishes between stative and agentive readings of Object Experiencer verbs and ascribes this distinction to the type of verbal morpheme with which the root is combined: it is either ''(standard) little v'' or a morpheme labeled as ''stative little v''. These ''little v'' morphemes are responsible for the syntactic effects such as reflexivization, causativization and extraction from the object (thus, in Italian, reflexivization is ungrammatical with the stative reading of the ObjExp verbs). Finally Arad proposes a preliminary typology of ''little v'' morphemes, basing on the assumption that these morphemes have three types of properties: verbalizing property (making a verb out of a category neutral root), semantic content (agentive, stative, inchoative, causative etc.) and transitivity. It is shown that languages may put together different sets of features into their ''little v'' morphemes. It is further generalised that the same root can form different types of ''verbs'' when combined with verbal morphemes of different types.

    In the following paper (''Agree or attract? A Relativized Minimality solution to a Proper Binding Condition puzzle''), Boeckx examines the 'how likely' paradigm starting with the contrast (=5 in Boeckx) originally reported in Kroch and Joshi (1985):

    1 a. How likely to win is John? but b. *How likely to be a riot is there?

    This contrast has been recently taken as an argument for feature- movement (Lasnik, 2002). However, Boeckx shows that Lasnik's analysis is inadequate in a number of ways, both empirically (further facts going against Lasnik's interpretation are provided) and conceptually. In contrast to previous solutions to the puzzle, Boeckx analysis shows that the contrast has nothing to do with remnant movement or the Proper Binding Condition (''traces must be bound''). In other words, cases like (1b) should be ruled out prior to the application of remnant movement. An alternative analysis deeply implicates Relativized Minimality; in particular, since 'how likely' is docomposable into a wh-part and indefinite part, it is the latter that creates an intervention and thus blocks the Agree between T and NP in (1b). By contrast, the cases like (1a) are rescued by the presence of a D-feature on the noun phrase being attracted, which allows Agree to succeed. In general, Boeckx' analysis captures the basic 'how-likely' paradigm without any appeal to remnant movement, distinct LF- component, or move-F, and ''[i]n so doing, [it] (...) lends credence to the conceptually more elegant mechanism of Agree and the One-cycle model of syntax (p. 58).

    Fanselow and Cavar's contribution (''Distributed deletion'') addresses the problem of NP- and PP-split constructions in Slavic and German, such as e.g. German. The following example is (5) in F&C): 2 Interessante Buecher hat sie mir keine aus Indien empfohlen interesting books has she me none from India recommended ''She has not recommended any interesting books from India to me''

    It is shown that XP-splits arise in the context of operator movement only; they can retain (Pull splits) or invert (Inverted splits) the order of the elements found in the continuous counterpart. The authors convincingly show that previous analyses (simple movement and base generation theories, first of all) face serious problems when applied to these constructions. On the one hand, the former approach cannot account for the (possible) repetition of phonetic material (e.g. prepositions) in imperfect splits and for the violation of standard islands for movement (e.g. PP-islands); on the other hand, the latter approach assuming base-generation of both parts in situ fail (among other things) to adequately describe some linear order facts that in fact call for the movement approach. The paradox is given solution within the copy and deletion approach to movement (see e.g. Chomsky 1995). The basic insight of F&C is that ''deletion may affect BOTH the upstairs AND the downstairs copy, but in a partial way so, which yields the split XP construction''. Such an approach seems to be a kind of compromise between simple movement and double base-generation and provides a unified analysis for both NP and PP splits.

    Frank, Hagstrom and Vijay-Shanker's article (''Roots, constituents and c-command'') addresses the problem of adequate syntactic representation and the primitive notions of such representation. The authors argue for the non-existence of primitive dominance (''dominance does not figure into grammatical explanation'' p.110); what they propose instead is the primitive status of c- command. They show how such notions as roots and constituents that have been traditionally defined with reference to dominance can be redefined with reference to c-command only. Such an approach leads to the distinction of ''the categorial root'' (the node that determines the category of the tree as a whole) and ''the attachment root'' (the node that provides the locus of cyclic attachment). With respect to the notion of constituency much effort is made in order to retain the validity of the claim that ''All and only constituents can be moved'' (e.g. p. 123). Again, constituency is re-defined without any reference to dominance. The basic idea of the article may be indeed very influential for the architecture of syntactic representation; it is shown that the approach adopted in the paper makes it possible to capture many generalisations with respect to such phenomena as movement, ellipsis and conjunction in an elegant and economic fashion. Finally, it is suggested as a theoretical possibility that ''perhaps constituency is verified at and useful for PF, while syntax (and even perhaps LF) are not sensitive to issues of constituency'' (p. 133).

    Kural's contribution to the volume (''A four-way classification of monadic verbs'') deals with the problems that emerge from the more or less commonly accepted view according to which such verbs can be divided into unaccusative and unergative verbs, as originally proposed by Perlmutter (1978). Further research (most notably Burzio 1986) has shown that unaccusative verbs are generated as internal arguments inside the VP, while unergative verbs are generated as external arguments outside the VP; besides, a bunch of tests associated with this distinction has been proposed in previous studies. In his paper, Kural takes up some seven of these tests, namely, there-insertion, locative inversion, subject case (ergative vs. nominative), agreement, and the possibility of cognate objects, resultatives and way-construction. It is argued that these tests ''do not all test the same structural properties'', and that ''the discrepancies in the behavior of some monadic verbs across these tests can be explained naturally by positing a four-way classification'' (p. 142). A distinct syntactic structure is proposed for each type of monadic verbs. While verbs of being and the change of location verbs have the same VP design as classic unaccusative and unergative verbs, respectively, the other two types of monadic verbs distinguished in the paper (namely, the change of state verbs and verbs of creation) are endowed with a complex multi-layered structure each involving an extra node (directional phrase and CAUSE phrase respectively). It is finally shown that the differences in syntactic structures typical of these verbs are tightly associated with their broad semantic properties.

    In the following paper (''On agreement. Locality and feature variation'', by Luis Lopez) a new approach to the operations Agree and Move is offered, that makes it possible to get rid of some unnecessary assumptions proposed earlier (e.g. ''freezing effects'' and Global Economy framework, that allows operations that can ''look ahead'' at future derivational steps). Instead, the principle of Locality of Agreement is maintained, that limits Agree to elements not separated by a maximal category. Quite traditionally, Agree is understood as an operation that co-values two sets of features. However, Lopez admits the possibility of Agree between two terms with unvalued features: ''[i]f both probe and goal have unvalued features of the same type, they will remain unvalued, with a twist: since they are now involved in the Agree relation, these features will be co-valued'' (p. 172). Contrarily to Chomsky (1999) and in agreement with the Locality of Agreement principle, movement is understood as a consequence of the ''tension'' in the system created by the inability of Agree between two items that are too distant for probing. These theoretical assumptions are successfully used in the analyses of structural case assignment, expletive constructions (a sketchy typology of those is provided) and movement chains. It is shown that feature co-valuation underlies these phenomena and that ultimately Case assignment is only a variant of the agreement relation.

    Mateu and Rigau (''A minimalist account of conflation processes. Parametric variation at the lexicon syntax interface'') undertake a minimalist analysis of conflation processes; they take Talmy's (1985) original analysis as a starting point of their investigation and acknowledge its descriptive adequacy. In particular, they acknowledge the fact that various languages may conflate semantic components like Figure, Motion, Path, Manner, or Cause into the verb in different ways. Thus, for instance, ''conflation of motion with path is argued to be typical of Romances [sic!] languages (...), whereas conflation of motion with manner is typical of English'' (p. 211). Mateu and Rigau's insight is to give these facts a basically syntactic explanation within a minimalist framework. For that purpose, they introduce a number of phonologically null verbs such as GO, CAUSE etc. that must be conflated (by means of simple Merge) with some other element with phonological properties. Conflation of a full verb (e.g. 'dance') with one or another phonologically null verb will lead to the different syntactic structures that in their turn correspond to some diagnostic constructions analyzed by Talmy. While the former verb expresses the manner component, the latter verb determines the cause/motion/state meaning of the construction. As a consequence, the cross-linguistic variation with respect to the conflation processes as analyzed by Talmy, is reinterpreted by Mateu and Rigau as an epiphenomenon of (un)availability of the relevant empty heads (CAUSE/GO/BE). The various syntactic phenomena involving path constructions and existential locative constructions are explained within this approach.

    Romero (''Morphological constraints on syntactic derivations'') addresses once again the problem of the sources of cross- linguistic variation. He argues that languages differ in the formal features they encode, although there is a universal set of features available for the faculty of language. This selection is idiosyncratic, although not completely arbitrary. The empirical data Romero discusses include the cases when Person-Case Constraint (PCC) is at work; this constraint states that dative arguments are ungrammatical if the accusative is first or second person, and agreement is overtly realized. Thus, Romero argues that PCC shows up only if there are agreement features involved. Romero's analyses of particular linguistic data aim at getting rid of ''looking-forward'' properties triggering computations, which is a desirable way of thinking for any minimalist study, since ''[i]f being (un)interpretable is an interface property, then it cannot be relevant troughout [sic] the derivation'' (p. 255).

    In the last contribution to the volume (Sabel, ''Intermediate traces, reconstruction and locality effects''), a Constraint on Adjunction Movement (CAM) is introduced, according to which ''[m]ovement may not proceed via intermediate adjunction'' (p. 260). To put it in a somewhat different way, this constraint suggests that whenever an element is moved to an adjoined position this element cannot move further and is ''frozen in place'' in this position. Or, to rephrase the constraint once again, movement can only proceed via specifier position. The article is organized in such a way that first, a bunch of phenomena are introduced that have been traditionally analyzed as cases of successive-cyclic movement via intermediate adjunction. These phenomena include weak crossover effects, locality phenomena and reconstruction properties of moved elements with respect to scope and binding properties. However, the in the following section the author argues that if ''the intermediate adjunction hypothesis holds, several ad hoc devices are needed to constraint the unrestricted use of this mechanism'' (p. 269) and that these devices are not independently motivated. Thus, an alternative interpretation for various movement types are offered, including wh-movement, quantifier raising, scrambling, A-movement, empty operator movement, and head movement. Some cases that have been traditionally used as an empirical basis for intermediate adjunction are reanalyzed with the help of multiple specifier positions.

    EVALUATION

    Overall, this volume is a valuable contribution to the study of the architecture of Universal Grammar (UG) and of the sources of cross-linguistic variation. Taken together, the contributions to the volume cover a wide range of theoretical problems (probably, at the expense of evident unity between the papers). Some of the papers provide very interesting insights in the study of particular syntactic phenomena (e.g. Arad, Kural, Mateu and Rigau) drawing attention to the previously unnoticed regularities in natural languages. The stress of some other papers is on the theoretical rather than empirical side; e.g. the papers by Boeckx, Frank & Vijay-Shanker, Lopez and Sabel address the issues that are very relevant for the development of the minimalist program; their theoretical claims may have a very far-reaching impact on the basic matters of the UG and can potentially appear to be very influential for the future research. This distinction is not meant to imply that theoretical issues in the contributions are kept apart from discovering challenging empirical regularities (a weighed balance between the two sides can be found in e.g. Fanselow and Cavar's contribution). Although there is a lot of controversy between the implications of particular papers (e.g. Sabel's contribution employs ''freezing effects'' in order to maintain his Constraint on Adjunction Movement, while one of the aims of Lopez's analysis consists in getting rid of these effects as they are considered to be unwelcome for the general ideology of the minimalist program), the volume is significant and useful in a variety of ways.

    My main reservation with respect to the volume is two-fold. First, I am not quite sure that the title of the volume (''Theoretical approaches to universals'') is fitting for its content. Indeed, the very word ''universal'' (as a noun) does not appear in the majority of papers; moreover, the question of the universality of particular phenomena is not directly addressed to in some of them, either. Rather, it is the problem of cross- linguistic variation that is discussed explicitly in some papers (Arad, Romero) and it is only through the analysis of particular constraints imposed upon this variation that the problem of universality is tackled. Of course, universality of the basic architecture of language is a prevailing principle for any minimalist researcher, but still the title of the volume may seem somewhat misleading.

    Second, the cross-linguistic dimension of the volume is not entirely convincing. It is explicitly stated in the introduction by the editor that the goals that are chosen in the volume can only be reached by comparative study of language. However, there are some papers that are almost exclusively concerned with the data from English (e.g. Boeckx' contribution). Many other contain basically a comparison of English and one or two more languages (e.g. German or Spanish). In general, the list of languages referred to in the volume does not have but some 25 entries, out of which only 10 are non-Indo-European languages and with only 7 languages spoken outside Europe, and only 3 outside Eurasia. In general, dealing with particular languages seems to be somewhat unprincipled and ad hoc in many cases. Moreover, there are a lot of inaccuracies in this respect. E.g. on page 117 we read ''(:) in certain Slavic languages, including Bulgarian and Romanian [sic]''. It may be further mentioned that both Bulgarian and Romanian are missing in the language index, although there are examples from both in the volume (besides, the example on the same page 117, and many others e.g. on page 251 are not properly introduced, as it is not indicated what is their language). Being a native speaker of Russian, I checked the three passages of the volume where Russian data are discussed and found that ALL OF THEM are not perfect (namely, the root is udiv- rather than udivl- in examples on page 34; a diacritic is missing in example (32) on page 225 and the unstarred examples on page 284 are at best to be marked as questionable according to my speaker's intuition.

    Of course, these critical remarks do not undermine the fact that the book under review could be highly recommended to anyone interested in the recent advances in the basic issues of the generative grammar.

    REFERENCES

    Burzio, L. 1986. Italian syntax. Dordrecht: Reidel publishing.

    Chomsky, N. 1995. The minimalist program. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Chomsky, N. 1999. Derivation by phase [MIT occasional papers in linguistics 18]. Department of linguistics and philosophy, MIT.

    Kroch, A. and A. Joshi. 1985. The linguistic relevance of tree- adjoining grammar. Ms., University of Pennsylvania.

    Lasnik, H. 2002. Feature movement or agreement at a distance? In: A.Alexiadou, E. Anagnostopoulou, S. Barbiers and H.-M. Gaertner (eds.). Dimensions of movement: From features to remnants. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.

    Perlmutter, D. 1978. Impersonal passive and the unaccusative hypothesis. In: Proceedings of the 4th annual meeting of the Berkeley linguistic society. UC Berkeley.

    Talmy, L. 1985. Lexicalization patterns: Semantic structures in lexical forms. In: T. Shopen (ed.). Language typology and syntactic description. Vol. 3. Grammatical categories and the lexicon. Cambridge: CUP. ABOUT THE REVIEWER

    Sergey Say is a post-graduate student/assistant of ILI RAN (Institute for linguistic research of the Russian Academy of Sciences), Saint- Petersburg. His academic interests include ellipsis, word order, semantics and structure of the argument structure, and other (morpho-)syntactic matters in the Russian and Baltic languages. His basic intent is to study these phenomena in an anthropologically- oriented, typologically-backgrounded perspective.