Review of Minimalist Syntax |
|
|
Review: |
Date: Fri, 18 Jun 2004 13:58:37 -0400 From: Justin Fitzpatrick Subject: Minimalist Syntax
EDITOR: Hendrick, Randall TITLE: Minimalist Syntax PUBLISHER: Blackwell Publishing YEAR: 2003
Justin M. Fitzpatrick, MIT
SUMMARY This book consists of five essays on different aspects of current research in minimalist syntax. All of the essays have a mixed review/new research character. That is, each attempts to couch cutting- edge research within a larger perspective, as well as serve as an introduction to such research for those who are not already familiar with it. Furthermore, most of the chapters highlight new and innovative analyses of old problems, dealt with at length in Government-Binding (GB) theory, using the tools and ideas made available in minimalism.
Chapter 1, Hornstein's ''On control'', discusses differences between control and raising, and the prospects that control can be treated as movement. Fox's ''On logical form'' (chapter 2) discusses fundamental issues in the treatment of quantificational NPs and presents Fox's own material on antecedent-contained deletion, extraposition, and the copy theory of movement. In chapter 3 Lasnik and Hendrick turn to binding theory and attempt to develop a theory of binding that makes no crucial reference to S-structure. Thrainsson's chapter 4 deals with cross- linguistic (including historical) differences with respect to verb movement. Thrainsson develops a theory that languages may differ in whether they have a split IP (T and Agr) or an atomic INFL. This difference is leveraged to explain observed differences across the Germanic languages. Finally, Chametsky turns to perhaps the most central of syntactic tools: phrase structure (PS). He provides detailed discussion and criticism of minimalist thought on PS, including close commentary on Chomsky (1995, 2000, 2001). Chametsky concludes that basic notions of PS from the early days of generative grammar through GB are incompatible with minimalism.
DISCUSSION Hendrick's introductory remarks provide brief and excellent historical and theoretic context for the rest of the book. Hendrick focuses on the minimalist application of a critical ''corrosive'' to our theories in the search for ''an elegant theory with the minimum of theoretical primitives and statements consistent with familiar goals of description and explanation.'' (pp. 2-3) and puts forth the idea that the shift from GB to minimalism is in part a shift from focus on representations to focus on rules (derivations), in ''an attempt to rethink many syntactic phenomena in the hopes of extracting greater insight by questioning the explanatory role of the representations.'' (p. 2)
This shift can be found clearly in Hornstein's analysis of control as movement (Chapter 1), where independently motivated NP-movement is recruited to do the job of representationally-defined construal in the control module of GB. Hornstein argues that pure base-generation in theta-position (as in GB, and more generally since Chomsky's ''Aspects'') should be abandoned. In essence, this move erases the last vestiges of D-structure from the theory and allows for movement into theta positions. Hornstein provides a short introduction to control phenomena, focusing on differences between control, raising, and exceptional case marking (ECM), as well as obligatory (OC) vs. non- obligatory control (NOC). He then investigates the results of treating OC as NP-movement, a theoretical option afforded him by the rejection of pure D-structure theta-role assignment, and NOC as a null pronoun (little pro). While this is an attractive proposal from the point of view of theoretical parsimony, Hornstein has his work cut out for him, as he himself acknowledges. While many of the shared characteristics of NP-movement and control are quickly explained, the differences present more of a challenge. Much of the second half of the chapter is devoted to providing (often new) answers to problems brought up by critics since Hornstein 1999, 2000, as well as extensions to backward control and so-called PRO-gate phenomena. Not all of the challenges are successfully met, however, and the reader need only glance at the rich literature concerning this debate (e.g. Culicover & Jackendoff 2001; Hornstein 1999, 2000; Landau 2000, 2003; Martin 1996, Grohmann 2003, inter alia) to see that the question is far from settled. However, the chapter serves as a good in depth introduction for those looking to dive into the polemic.
In chapter 2 Danny Fox discusses the semantics of quantificational noun phrases (QNPs) within truth-functional semantics of a (locally) compositional nature. Fox's main goal is to pursue a treatment of QNPs using syntactic movement and in the process incorporate complex data regarding binding and reconstruction within current conceptions of the copy theory of movement. Fox quickly establishes two key questions given the assumption that QNPs denote second-order properties that take one-place predicates as arguments (sister to the QNP): (i) How does a QNP find its argument when its sister is not a one-place predicate? (ii) How are arguments determined in constructions that involve multiple quantificational elements so as to account for scopal ambiguities? (p. 85). He then shows how overt QNP movement effects scope in the desired way and extends this result to covert quantifier raising (QR). This chapter provides an excellent introduction to the syntax/semantics of QNPs, and Fox is careful to note (and cite!) alternate approaches to the problems at hand. The second half of the article presents newer work (some along the lines of Fox & Nissenbaum 1999) that attempts to reconcile the copy theory of movement with antecedent-contained deletion (ACD) and binding theory effects by treating ACD through rightward extraposition.
Lasnik and Hendrick's chapter on binding theory nicely complements the first two chapters. They begin with a discussion of binding in control, raising, and ECM constructions, which are also discussed in chapter 1, and they go on to discuss reconstruction effects and the copy theory of movement along the lines introduced by Fox in chapter 2. They then extend the discussion to idiom interpretation and negative polarity item (NPI) licensing, among other things. Lasnik and Hendrick are largely concerned with establishing a version of binding theory that can account for the rich data related to binding without reference to S-structure or government, two constructs that are generally rejected in current minimalist work. They propose instead a ''clause-mate'' restriction (Postal 1974) on local anaphors at LF and make crucial use of Fox's ''determiner replacement'' and ''variable insertion'' operations on copies. Under this approach different LF mechanisms can access different occurrences of a syntactic object (different ''members of a chain'') at LF. The chapter moves rather quickly and introduces a large amount of data. Therefore, it is best appreciated if the reader is already steeped in the binding literature.
Focusing on Germanic languages, Thrainsson addresses cross-linguistic variation in verb raising in chapter 4. Some work in minimalist syntax has been marred by illusory ''explanations'' in terms of feature strength. The argument might go, for example, ''language A has verb raising because T has `strong features' and language B does not have verb raising because T's features are `weak'.'' Thrainsson rightly notes that this just restates the problem. Building on cross-linguistic (including historical) work, Thrainsson develops a theory to explain variation in verb raising through the inventory of inflectional heads in a given language. Specifically, languages with distinct T(ense) and Agr(eement) heads have verb raising while those with a single INFL head do not. That is, some languages have a ''split IP'' (Pollock 1989) and some do not. Thrainsson approaches the problem, as one should, from the point of view of the learner: how does a child learn what type of language she is learning? Thrainsson proposes that verb-adverb order and/or distinct tense and agreement morphemes will trigger a split-INFL hypothesis, while atomic INFL is the default. This correctly predicts that ''rich inflection'' and verb raising are not related biconditionally.
Thrainsson stresses this often-missed fact: If a language has rich inflection, it has verb raising, but it is not true that if a language does not have rich inflection, it does not have verb raising. Instead, there are examples of languages (e.g., dialects of Norwegian, Swedish, and Finnish, as well as Faroese) that have verb raising (at least in some clauses) without ''rich'' inflection. Thrainsson also presents synchronic work with modern Faroese speakers and suggests a historical sequence through which languages lose inflection and verb raising, but the former precedes the latter. Faroese appears to be a case in which both options are still available (though with difference across clause types): sometimes clauses have split INFL, sometimes they don't. While Thrainsson's specific proposal regarding why verb movement is necessary in split INFL but not in atomic INFL may have problems (for example, if AgrO is allowed in ''atomic'' INFL domains, or if negation heads its own projection), this proposal is a good example of responsible theoretical work on cross- linguistic (and intra-linguistic) variation and change.
Chametsky's chapter on phrase structure (PS) is perhaps the most polemical in the volume. Chametsky's main goal is to show that the following syllogism holds: (i) If there are lexical projections, then there are functional projections. (ii) There are no functional projections. (iii) Therefore, there are no lexical projections.
That is, minimalist syntax cannot be phrase structural. Since it is usually assumed without argument that phrase structure is basic and given, this argument has to be made very carefully. Chametsky does this by closely scrutinizing definitions and discussion in Chomsky (1995, 2000, 2001), Epstein et al. (1998), and Speas (1990), among others. In the process, he provides biting (and as far as I can tell correct) criticism of, e.g., Chomsky's (2001) treatment of adjunction and c- command. As close exegesis and criticism of work on the formal foundations of minimalist syntax, the chapter is a must-read. However, as a difficult argument (both for the writer and the reader), the reader would have been better served with a less circuitous argument and more discussion of non-phrase structural alternatives within minimalism. Chametsky does provide some discussion of alternatives, including that of Epstein et al. (1998) and Collins & Ura (2001), but, as Chametsky predicts, many will remain unconvinced. Most, however, should be shaken a bit from their dogmatic slumber.
This book attempts to provide about a 50/50 split between review of linguistic analysis within a given chapter's field and treatment of new leading ideas in the minimalist framework. In this goal it is largely successful, though readers must be warned that half of a short article cannot hope to do justice to many decades' worth of research in generative syntax. Familiarity is assumed throughout with basic syntactic concepts and GB theory. Therefore, the book would not be suitable as an introductory text to minimalism unless students had a good background in GB (and some minimalism!). Still, it would be a useful tool in an advanced seminar on minimalism or as a stepping stone to the rich primary literature that is cited throughout.
REFERENCES Chomsky, Noam. 1995. The minimalist program. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Chomsky, Noam. 2000. Minimalist inquiries: The framework. In Step by step, ed. by Roger Martin, David Michaels, and Juan Uriagereka, 89-156. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Chomsky, Noam. 2001. Derivation by phase. In Ken Hale: A life in language, ed. by Michael Kenstowicz, 1-52.
Collins, C. and H. Ura. 2001. Eliminating phrase structure. Ms., Cornell & Kwansei Gakuin University.
Culicover, Peter and Ray Jackendoff. 2001. Control is not movement. Linguistic Inquiry 32:493-511.
Epstein, Samuel David, Erich Groat, Ruriko Kawashima, and Hisatsugu Kitahara. 1998. A derivational approach to syntactic relations. New York: Oxford University Press.
Fox, Danny and Jon Nissenbaum. 1999. Extraposition and scope: A case for overt QR. In the Proceedings of WCCFL 18.
Grohmann, Kleanthes. 2003. Prolific domains: On the anti-locality of movement dependencies. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.
Hornstein, Norbert. 1999. Movement and Control. Linguistic Inquiry 11:679-708.
Hornstein, Norbert. 2000. Move! A minimalist theory of construal. Oxford: Blackwell.
Landau, Idan. 2000. Elements of control: Structure and meaning in infinitival constructions. Dordrecht: Kluwer.
Landau, Idan. 2003. Movement out of control. Linguistic Inquiry 34: 471-498.
Martin, Roger. 1996. A minimalist theory of PRO and control. Ph.D. dissertation, University of Connecticut, Storrs.
Pollock, Jean-Yves. 1989. Verb movement, universal grammar, and the structure of IP. Linguistic Inquiry 20:365-424.
Postal, Paul. 1974. On raising: One rule of English grammar and its theoretical implications. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Speas, M. 1990. Phrase structure in natural language. Dordrecht: Kluwer.
|
|
ABOUT THE REVIEWER:
ABOUT THE REVIEWER Reviewer's research interests: Locality and multi-dominance in syntax, computational learning theories of reduplication and verbal inflection, phonological cyclicity, the morpho-syntax of affixation, tense and aspect at the syntax-semantic interface. |
|
Versions: |
Format: |
Paperback |
ISBN: |
0631219412 |
ISBN-13: |
N/A
|
Pages: |
248 |
Prices: |
U.S. $
36.95
|
Format: |
Hardback |
ISBN: |
0631219404 |
ISBN-13: |
N/A
|
Pages: |
248 |
Prices: |
U.S. $
73.95
|
|
|
|
|