''English Verb Classes and Alternations: A Preliminary Investigation.'' By Beth Levin. Chicago and London: The University of Chicago Press, 1993. Pp. xviii, 348.
Reviewed by T. Daniel Seely, Eastern Michigan University.
Beth Levin's ''English Verb Classes and Alternations: A Preliminary Investigation'' (hence- forth EVC) is an excellent reference book. It presents syntactic and semantic information which is valuable and easy to use. The book is rich in well-organized data (there are thousands of entries in the verb index and the bulk of the book is made up of dozens of diathesis alternations and verb classes), it is thoroughly documented (there are some 800 references), and it has important theoretical implications (nicely traced in the Introduction). It is, in short, an impressive accomplishment and it has become an indispensable part of my linguistics library. EVC is a ''set of resource materials'' which can be used in a great many ways (more on that later). But it is not just a disconnected list of verb alternations and semantic subgroupings. Rather, it represents a well-conceived enterprise whose overall coherence can be found in the ''hypothesis of semantic determination,'' viz
(1) The meaning of a verb determines its syntactic behavior.
[Important corollaries of (1) are:
a. If the members of a set of verbs S share some meaning component M, then the members of S can be expected to exhibit the same syntactic behavior(s), and
b. If the members of a set of verbs S exhibit the same syntactic behavior(s), then the members of S can be expected to share some meaning component(s)]
This hypothesis is the book's guide, an extensive elaboration of its requirements and implications is the book's substance. The Introduction to EVC, for example, presents, illustrates, and defends (1), Part I systematizes many of the syntactic behaviors (verb alternations) relevant to it, and Part II contains some of the ''... semantically coherent verb classes'' that result from using it as a probe for ''linguistically relevant aspects of verb meaning'' (an exploitation of(1)b). That is the frame, let me now add some of the picture. As is made clear in the Introduction, (1) is controversial but worth pursuing; controversial in light of apparent counterexamples, but worth pursuing because
(2)a. some of the counterexamples turn out on closer inspection to actually support it,
b. it has important theoretical implications regarding the nature and content of the lexicon, and
c. it gives rise to a powerful research tool.
The very readable Introduction covers each of these points; I summarize below. The counter-example that Levin considers, from Rosen (1984), is this: The Italian verbs ''russare'' (snore) and ''arrossire'' (blush) share the meaning component ''bodily process'' while exhibiting disparate syntactic behavior--the former is unergative, the latter unaccusative. (1) must therefore be wrong. As for the defense, Levin argues that the case is damaging only if there is reason for assuming that ''...the semantic notion ''bodily process'' plays a part in determining a verb's status with respect to the Unaccusative Hypothesis.'' As it turns out, there are other semantic components of these verbs (involving activity vs change of state) which predict divergent behavior and which arguably do relate to the Unaccusative Hypothesis. Further details need not concern us here (indeed, the discussion in the Introduction on this point is essentially review of other work, by Levin et al and others). The more general point is that (1) requires determining the appropriate meaning components, something which while necessary is not always easy. [Moreover, maintaining (1) in the face of apparent counter-examples encourages us to look for, and perhaps discover, meaning components which might not have emerged otherwise.] Turning now to (2)b, the theoretical implications of the hypothesis of semantic determination are important indeed. A traditional view of the lexicon is wonderfully captured by Di Sciullo and Williams (1987). ''The lexicon,'' they write, ''is like a prison--it contains only the lawless, and the only thing that its inmates have in common is lawlessness.''
[NOTE that Levin herself gives the earlier and somewhat less vivid statement of Bloomfield (1933): ''The lexicon is really an appendix of the grammar, a list of basic irregularities.'' I use the Di Sciullo-Williams' quote (with full realization that there are great differences between Bloomfield and Di Sciullo-Williams) because I like it a great deal but also to set acontext for a mild criticism. Although EVC has a tremendous bibliography, there are a number of conspicuous gaps. There is no referenceto Di Sciullo and Williams, for instance. Nor is there reference to work on s- and c-selection by Grimshaw (1979) and Pesetsky (1982), work which is clearly and directly relevant to (1).]
Continuing our main discussion, lexical information should be minimized. If (1) is true, lexical information can be minimized in rather dramatic fashion. As Levin explains (and I quote here somewhat extensively to give the reader a feel for Levin's very accessible style)
If the syntactic properties of a verb indeed follow in large part from its meaning, then it should be possible to identify general principles that derive the behavior of a verb from its meaning. Given such principles, the meaning of a verb will clearly have a place in its lexical entry, but it is possible that the entry will need to contain little more. And since a word's meaning is necessarily idiosyncratic, the inclusion of a word's meaning in its lexical entry conforms to Bloomfield's characterization of the lexicon as a locus of idiosyncrasy. (p. 11)
And a bit later Levin summarizes:
Taking this approach seriously requires a re-evaluation of previous assumptions concerning the contents of lexical entries, since it suggests that they may contain less information than has sometimes been proposed. Specifically, if there are indeed correlations between verb meaning and verb behavior, some properties that might have been included in lexical entries because they were thought to be idiosyncratic could turn out on further examination to be predictable from verb meaning and could be eliminated from a verb's lexical entry. (p. 12)
Much recent work, as Levin notes, considers these conceptually very satisfying ideas. Levin's work represents a significant step in creating the empirical basis for realizing them. (2)c, the final point, is that the hypothesis of semantic determination gives rise to a powerful research tool. What this amounts to is an exploitation of (1)b. If the members of some set of verbs behave alike with respect to diathesis alternations (i.e. if they exhibit the same syntactic behavior), then there should be some meaning component which they have in common. And ''the availability of this technique for investigating word meaning is important since it can be quite difficult to pin down the meanings of words using introspection alone.'' (p 15) The members of the set of verbs {CUT, hack, saw,...}, for example, participate in the same alternations. Using ''cut'' as the representative case, they are found in the middle construction (3), the conative alternation (4), and the body-part possessor ascension alternation (5):
(3)a. Kimi cut the bread b. Bread cuts quite easily.
(4)a. Kimi cut the bread. b. Kimi cut at the bread.
(5)a. Kimi cut Bill's arm. b. Kimi cut Bill on the arm.
This contrasts with the sets {BREAK, crack, rip, shatter, snap, ...}, {TOUCH, pat, stroke, tickle, ...}, and {HIT, bask, kick, tap, ...}. Using the uppercase verb as the representative, the following pattern of behavior emerges (I use Levin's convenient table in the interest of space, the reader can easily plug in the relevant examples):
TOUCH HIT CUT BREAK Conative: No Yes Yes No Body-Part Ascension: Yes Yes Yes No Middle: No No Yes Yes
Levin then shows that these sets have common meaning components. Simplifying, the BREAK group doesn't require contact nor motion but does involve change of state. The CUT group requires contact and motion; Hit requires contact and motion but is not change of state, and TOUCH needs contact, no motion, and is not change of state. Overall, then, there is a clear relation between the syntactic behavior and key elements of meaning. And it is also clear that without the syntactic pattern as a guide, we might not have grouped the words together to look for the shared meaning. Consequently, Levin's research tool bears fruit. Levin's book is rich in detail and it points toward extremely fruitful further research. The issues above are important as is the book's more general aim of ''[paving] the way toward the development of a theory of lexical knowledge.'' Progress can be made only if the foundations are put into place. Levin's book is a solid foundation indeed.
As a final note, let me point out that although my comments have focussed on (some of) Levin's theoretical underpinnings, I have found many practical uses for the book. It has helped in making up exercise sets for syntax, semantics, and morphology classes, for example, it made checking the verbs of example sentences in a psycholinguistic study much easier, and it has been invaluable (my student's tell me) for creating exercises of various sorts in TESOL. It is, after all, a reference work and like all good references it is limited only by the imagination of its user. At one point Levin states ''... I hope that [this book] will be a valuable resource for linguists and researchers inrelated fields.'' A hope most certainly realized!
REFERENCES
Bloomfield, L. (1933) ''Language,'' Holt, New York. Di Sciullo, A. M., and E. Williams (1987) ''On the Definition of Word,'' Linguistic Inquiry Monograph 14, MIT Press, Cambridge. Grimshaw, J. (1979) ''Complement Selection and the Lexicon,'' Linguistic Inquiry 10, 279-326. Pesetsky, D. (1982) ''Paths and Categories,'' MIT dissertation. Rosen, C. (1984) ''The Interface between Semantic Roles and Initial Grammatical Relations,'' in D. M. Perlmutter and C. Rosen, (eds) (1984) ''Studies in Relational Grammar 2,'' University of Chicago Press, Chicago, Il.
|