L�deling, Anke (2001) On Particle Verbs and Similar Constructions in German. Stanford: CSLI. (http://csli- publications.stanford.edu/site/1575863022.html)
Reviewer: Andrew McIntyre, University of Leipzig.
Constructions like _work out, hang around, eat up_, and their counterparts in other Germanic languages, known as 'phrasal verbs', 'separable verbs', 'verb-particle combinations' and, in German-speaking circles, as 'particle verbs', have inspired much literature, recent large-scale studies being Deh� 2001, Deh� et al. 2001, den Dikken 1995, McIntyre 1998, Olsen 1998, Stiebels 1996, Toivonen 2001, Zeller 1999. It is unclear how we should describe the syntactic, morphological, semantic and argument structural properties of particle verbs (hereafter: pv's), which is a pity, because a correct approach would teach us much about the structure of the verb phrase and about the interfaces between semantics, syntax and morphology.
Anke L�deling (hereafter: L) presents a well written study of the German constructions. Her perspective is that 'there are no particle verbs' (p. ix). The objects usually bearing that name have neither a unique nor a uniform syntactic structure. Some are seen as V' structures (analogous to one common treatment of resultative constructions), while, in a novel move, L treats other particles (along with object depictive predicates and certain adverbials) as adjuncts to V'. L uses the term 'particle (verb)' as shorthand for 'an object usually called a 'particle (verb)', and I will do so too.
CHAPTER 1 introduces the basic problems studied by L, viz. the problem of the structure of pv's and that of how and whether pv's should be distinguished from other constructions. The latter aim involves clarifying the nature of 'particles'. While other authors posit a definition for 'particle', L argues that there is no natural class corresponding to the term (Section 1.2.2).
It is argued that pv-like structures with nominal and verbal nonheads are distinct from pv's by virtue of e.g. their apparent unproductivity and inability to be input for derivational processes. This is at variance with the rest of the study, which downplays the importance of these phenomena as criteria for distinguishing pv's from other structures, but the inconsistency is not detrimental to L's general analysis.
L (p. 15-18) dismisses the idea that particles are intransitive prepositions, but I query some of the arguments (without wishing to claim that all particles are prepositional). L sees the intransitive preposition view of particles as problematic because intransitive prepositions 'by definition only have one argument and thus cannot introduce arguments in addition to the arguments of the verb' (p.17). I disagree: an 'intransitive' preposition is one which does not case-mark a complement, and this is compatible with cases where it contributes an external argument (=theme, trajector, figure), as in _vote a government in_ (cf. *_vote a government_), or even an internal argument (=reference object, landmark, ground), as in _run someone over, pour the bucket out_.
L (p.17) also argues that many core particles (e.g. the German cognates of 'in, out, off, up, on') were 'originally all adverbs and have changed their category over time' and that their semantics (e.g. their assumed ability to act as functors over the verb) might retain this adverbial character. Here L. seems to be using 'adverb' in the traditional sense, which lumps together adjective-related elements like _schnell_ 'quick(ly)' with complementless directional/locational elements, even though the latter are for the most part formally related to complement-taking prepositions and share many of their distributional properties. One could query the usefulness of this taxonomy. The traditional use of 'adverb' smacks strongly of being a repository for unclassified elements, and cannot legitimately be appealed to as a primitive category without discussion. Anyway, the 'adverbs' which were the ancestors of today's particles would still be called 'intransitive prepositions' by most people using that label. We miss generalizations if we deny the prepositional character of the core particles in German. For instance, they pattern with prepositional phrases in freely forming unaccusative directional constructions (_einsteigen_ 'get in' vs. _in den Zug steigen_ 'get in the train'), while, as L, p.148, fn 114 notes, German does not easily form unaccusative resultatives with AP predicates: German cannot literally render _the toast burnt black_ or _the butter melted soft_.
While I queried L's arguments against the existence of a natural class corresponding to any normal use of the term 'particle', familiarity with the full inventory of particles in German (including some exotica mentioned at the end of this review) leads to the conclusion that no satisfactory definition and classification of German particles has been arrived at, and that it is reasonable to assume that 'particles' are not a grammatical primitive, but rather a set of entities behaving uniformly with respect to some, but not all, of a set of more primitive parameters, such as their category, their ability to project phrases, their position within VP, their ability to predicate over a NP, etc.
CHAPTER 2 examines syntactic, semantic and phonological properties of German pv's, highlighting problems with the morphological view of pv formation. Some supposedly 'morphological' effects of particles (idiomatic semantics, fiddling with verbal selection restrictions) are found with structures unilaterally treated as phrasal structures (e.g. resultatives). Being separable, pv's have no place in any normal lexicalist view of morphology. Particle topicalization and modification are attestable and cases where they are blocked do not bespeak deference to lexical integrity but a lack of semantic independence of the particle. L's arguments here are echoed in several other studies (e.g. Kayne 1984:125, Booij 1990, McIntyre 1998, Zeller 1999). Some may feel that arguing at length against the traditional arguments for the morphological view of pv formation is belaboring the obvious, but I support L on this score because some linguists generating pv's in the morphology have ignored the counterarguments in the literature, failing to realize that they have the burden of proof and must either (a) find new evidence for their position (Olsen 2000, McIntyre 1998 attempted this) or (b) supplement the traditional arguments with an expanded view of morphology which can duplicate the same surface structures as syntax (e.g. resultative constructions and idioms like the capitalized material in _she COULD have clearly DONE WITH some help_ or_THE CHIPS ARE DOWN_). Option (b) is implausible, but is a logical consequence of using some traditional arguments for the morphological view of pv's.
Of course, it is possible that pv's are exceptional morphological objects or that the normal signs of lexical integrity, notably inseparability, have been overrated. But whether pv's give sufficient evidence to warrant exploring such possibilities is an open question.
CHAPTER 3 discusses another standard argument for the view that pv's are morphological objects, based on the fact that German pv's readily act as input to derivational morphology, coupled with the No Phrase Constraint, which bans phrases as input to morphology. L. adduces empirical evidence against the No Phrase Constraint, and argues that cases where an affix attaches to pv's but not to resultative constructions do not reflect a structural difference. Section 3.4 explores various German affixes and their compatibility with pv's and resultative constructions. 3.4.1 gives some convincing pragmatic constraints on the use of agentive suffix _er_ , which explain cases like the _anstreicher_ 'painter' (based on a pv) vs. *_rotstreicher_ 'person who paints sth. red'. The circumfix _Ge...e_ (p. 103ff) is discussed, but no explanation is given for why it does not hapilly attach to resultative constructions.
Cases where the affixes _-ung_ 'event nominaliser', _-bar_ '-able' and _un-_ 'un-' attach to pv's but not resultative constructions are argued to be sensitive not to putative structural differences between the constructions, but to whether or not the affix' input is lexically listed. This is potentially significant, but I use the hedge advisedly, since L discusses only a very small data sample, and readers cannot assess the accuracy of L's claim without collecting data themselves. Assuming the proposal is correct, it is interesting and one would have welcomed more discussion of the questions it raises. I mention two. Firstly, it is sometimes claimed that the listing of fully regular constructions is possible if they are frequent (e.g. Jackendoff 1997:122f). Perhaps L can appeal to this to explain certain cases where apparently fully compositional pv's can be suffixed with some of L's putative listing-sensitive affixes (examples attested by internet search are _Heraustrennung_ 'separating out', _herausnehmbar_ 'take-out-able', _zusammenklappbar_ 'fold- up-able'). If further work confirms L's hypothesis, then the affixes involved would be a useful test for cases where we are not sure if a compositional structure is listed or not, although getting round the potential circularity would need careful argumentation. Secondly, why are there affixes which attach to complex verbs only if they are listed? We know that affixes often stipulate conditions on the semantics, phonology, category or morphological structure of their bases. Is the listedness of the base another requirement which affixes can just stipulate? Or is there some deeper principle behind L's observation? We might consider asking whether the putatively listing-sensitive processes are constrained e.g. in the following way: (a) they operate presyntactically (b) they can attach to a non-minimal verbal projection This predicts that the affixes can only attach to phrasal V-projections already existing when the affixation applies, precisely those which are listed. (Affixes like _-er_ allowing unlisted input would lack requirement (a).)
Of course, (a) and (b) are, as they stand, stipulations from hell, but if a case can be made for their empirical necessity elsewhere, then we would be closer to a more explanatory account of L's observations. Whether or not this is a good approach, it seems worthwhile to ask whether the listedness requirement of the affixes under consideration can be made to follow from something else. Attempts at answering this question might benefit from asking whether there are affixes which require complex bases which are NOT listed. If there are no such affixes, we must explain why words and listed phrases behave like a natural class as far as some (but not all) affixes are concerned. If there are such affixes, then listedness sensitivity is probably just stipulated by the affixes. (I do not know whether there are such affixes. The nearest thing to a relevant case I can think of is the suggestion of Raffelsiefen 1992:157-160 that compositional/ productive _un-_ prefixation of English adjectives is possible only when the bases are productively derived adjectives (_unfriendly_ but *_unnice_), but this is not the same thing as requiring unlisted input.) In sum, Chapter 3 presents a potentially significant proposal (perhaps the most significant in the book) which needs further empirical support and theoretical clarification, aims which the author is pursuing, cf. L�deling/de Jong 2001). I close discussion of the chapter by noting a less central issue. The analysis of _un-_ prefixation (p. 109-113) either has interesting consequences or is problematic. The acceptability difference in (2a-b) is claimed to follow from the listedness of the pv 'abschick-' and the nonlistedness of 'wegschick-'. However, even if we agree that these pv's differ in terms of listedness, there is the additional complication that _un-_ has to attach to an adjectival participle formed from the pv, and the listedness of _abschick-_ does not automatically entail the listing of the adjectival participle formed from it. (Note that both pv's can form adjectival participles (cf. (2c)), although informants find _abgeschickt_ better than _weggeschickt_ in this construction.)
(2) a. der Brief ist unabgeschickt 'the letter is un-sent- off' b. *der Brief ist unweggeschickt 'the letter is un- sent-away' c. der Brief ist abgeschickt/weggeschickt 'the letter is sent off/away'
To solve this puzzle convincingly, L must do either of the following things: (a) show that the adjectival participle of the pv _abschick-_ 'send off' is listed. (I see no evidence for this.) (b) assess the implications of assuming that _un-_ prefixation is constrained such that, if it attaches to an adjective zero-derived from a past participle which itself is derived from a complex verb, the complex verb must be listed. It might be objected that this flies in the face of generalisations to the effect that morphological processes only refer to information present in the immediately preceding derivational step (e.g. the Adjacency Condition, Bracketing Erasure), for L's analysis of (2b) suggests that _un-_ prefixation is sensitive to the listing of a structure which has undergone two subsequent morphological operations whose output is not listed. Even though the Adjacency Condition has rightly been criticised by various authors (e.g. Raffelsiefen 1992), one would have welcomed some discussion of the issue. Here L is too modest: she underestimates the potential significance of her own suggestion. Apart from its consequences for the question as to what types of information morphological processes can refer to, perhaps L could have commented on the implications of her analysis for Kratzer's quite influential (1994) theory, which bases certain arguments on the contrast in (2).
CHAPTER 4 surveys some earlier proposals on pv structure. CHAPTER 5 presents L's syntactic analyses for pv's and related constructions. Some pv's (let us call them 'resultative pv's') are given the same structure as resultative constructions, and are analyzed as V' structures, while in other cases, the particles are seen as V' adjuncts (like object depictive predicates and certain adverbials). Various proposals exist for differing structures for pv's (Kratzer 1994, Aarts 1989, Wurmbrand 2000, Harley/Noyer 1997), though none resembles L's proposal for V' adjunction for some particles. The idea that (most) pv's are structurally identical to resultative constructions has many precedents in the literature (e.g. Hoekstra 1988, Haider 1997, Winkler 1994:388), and L's choice of a V' structure for these is a standard strategy if one rejects the small clause approach and the morphological one (cf. Haider, Winkler, Zeller 1999). I have little to say on this part of the analysis, except that L (p.148-55) provides some convincing remarks explaining certain syntactic differences between the pv's and resultatives for which the uniform V' analysis is proposed.
Very few instances of the putative type of particle adjoined to V' are discussed (p. 156 exhausts the data sample), so it is hard to know which particles are V' adverbials in L's scheme of things. Most are so-called 'aspectual' particle uses. I will try to show that aspectual particles are bad candidates for such an analysis, although there are particles for which L's adjunction analysis might be valid. One particle treated as an adjunct is a use of _an_ in forming verbs expressing partial affectedness like those in (3).
(3) _andiskutieren_ 'discuss partly', _anlesen_ 'read partly'
L (p. 144, 156) assumes, I think rightly, that adjuncts do not change the argument structure of the verb. However, pv's exhibiting the use of _an_ seen in (3) are always obligatorilly transitive (Stiebels 1996:78f, Zeller 1997, McIntyre 2001a:152ff), even if the simplex verb is optionally transitive (as are those in (3)). Moreover, the particle can introduce objects of types not allowed by the simplex verb:
(4a) _einen Plan andenken_ 'think about a plan in a preliminary fashion' (4b) _*einen Plan denken_
Facts like these lead Zeller 1997 and McIntyre 2001a to argue that this use of _an_ is not (as L assumes) an inchoative marker behaving like a functor over the verb, but a secondary predicate signalling partial affectedness of the direct object. If so, the intuitition that _an_ conveys the beginning of an event is epiphenomenal. This initially surprising assumption gains plausibility when we consider another German particle also traditionally analysed as an inchoative marker, _los_. Unlike _an_, it forbids direct objects:
(4'a) _ich sang Lieder_ 'I sang songs' (4'b) _ich sang *(Lieder) AN__ 'I sang parts of songs' (4'c) _ich sang (*Lieder) LOS_ 'I started singing (songs)'
There are at least a dozen Germanic particle uses which likewise block direct objects (e.g. _fight (*one's enemies) on_, _hammer (*the metal) around_, _sing (*jazz) along_), cf. McIntyre (2001a,b) and Stiebels (1996:64f) for attempts at an explanation. These are the particles where L's functor analysis is arguably most apposite, but they affect the argument structure radically. The other group of 'aspectual' particles includes _an_ and all 'perfective' particle uses. These convey information about the lexical aspect of an event indirectly by specifying how the event affects an incremental theme, which appears as a direct object (often obligatory, often flouting verbal selection restrictions). In either case, aspectual particles ride roughshod over a verb's argument structure in a way that adverbials and depictive predicates do not. This undermines one of L's reasons for assuming the adjunction analysis in the first place.
L must also explain some syntactic differences between depictives/adverbials and the particles treated as V' adjuncts. One is that the putative adjoined particles behave like resultative particles and differently from depictives in insisting on verb-adjacency in verb cluster formation in standard German:
(5a) weil sie das Fleisch wird [KALT/AUF]ESSEN wollen because she the meat will [COLD/UP]EAT want 'because she will want to eat the meat cold/up' (5b) weil sie das Fleisch [KALT/*AUF] wird ESSEN wollen because she the meat [cold/up]will EAT want
Further evidence bearing on the particles-qua-adjuncts hypothesis might come from prosody (cf. Winkler 1994 on depictives vs. resultatives), but the prosodic facts concerning particles and other secondary predicates are too subtle to judge without pitch extraction data.
There are some particles which are more likely to be adjuncts than are aspectual particles. I mention them, along with some problems they raise for L's theory (and every other pv theory I know):
1. _vor_ and _nach_ in the readings 'beforehand' and 'afterwards, re-'. These are always called particles and preserve the verb's argument structure. One might want to treat them as adjuncts on a par with the synonymous adverbs _vorher_ 'beforehand' and _nachher_ 'afterwards'. But pairs like _vorbestellen_/_vorher bestellen_ 'order beforehand' do not show a uniform syntactic behaviour e.g. in tests parallel to (5). 2. _wieder_ 'again' behaves syntactically and prosodically like a resultative particle when it has narrow scope, except that it can co-occur with other particles (_wieder aufbauen_ 'reconstruct'). Stechow (1996) adjoins this use of _wieder_ to a small clause. 3. Some uses of _mit_ 'with'. It can form idioms with verbs (_mitteilen_ "with-divide", 'inform', _mitkriegen_ "with-get", 'hear about') which pattern like resultative pv's with respect to stress and syntactic behaviour, although there is no hint of a resultative meaning. If _mit_ relates to the verb compositionally, it can behave either like _mit_ in idiomatic combinations, or else like a defocussed adverbial and may be separated from the verb in contexts where particles cannot:
(6a) MIT im Team SPIELEN WITH in.the team PLAY 'play with the others in the team' (6b) im Team MITSPIELEN in.the team WITH-PLAY 1. 'play with the others in the team' 2. 'cooperate in the team (not necessarily a sporting team)'
Since none of these, except _wieder_, has received a theoretically informed and empirically representative treatment, discussing them would have been worthwhile, if only to expand the book's empirical focus, which concentrates on types of pv's which have been discussed elsewhere (e.g. Stiebels 1996, Zeller 1999). Introducing new and difficult data into theoretical arenas can only be beneficial.
REFERENCES Aarts, Bas (1989), "Verb-preposition constructions and small clauses in English", in: Journal of Linguistics 25:277-290.
Booij, G., 1990. The boundary between morphology and syntax. Yearbook of Morphology 3, 45-63.
Deh�, N, Jackendoff, R., McIntyre, A., and Urban S., (eds.) 2001. Verb particle explorations. Mouton de Gruyter. (to appear)
Deh�, N. 2001. Syntactic, phonological and information structural aspects of English particle verbs. Diss. Leipzig.
den Dikken, M., 1995. Particles. Oxford University Press. Haider, H. 1997: "Precedence among predicates", Journal of Comparative Germanic Linguistics 1, 3-41.
Harley, H., & Noyer, R., 1997. Mixed nominalisations, short verb movement and object shift. NELS 28.
Hoekstra, T, 1988. Small clause results. Lingua 74:101-39.
Kayne, R. 1984, "Principles of Particle Constructions", in: Gu�ron, Jacqueline, H.-G. Obenauer (eds.), Grammatical Representations, Dordrecht: Foris, S. 101-140.
Kratzer, A., 1994. The event argument and the semantics of voice. Ms. Amherst.
L�deling, A. and de Jong, N. 2001. Particle verbs and word formation. To appear in Deh� et al. (eds.)
McIntyre, A. 1998: German double particles as preverbs. Diss. Sydney. To appear with Stauffenburg (T�bingen).
McIntyre, A, 2001a: "Argument blockages induced by verb particles". In Nicole Deh� and Anja Wanner (eds.) Structural Aspects of Semantically Complex Verbs. Berlin: Peter Lang. 131-164.
McIntyre, A. 2001b. Preverbs, argument linking and verb semantics. Ms Leipzig (www.uni-leipzig.de/~angling/olsen/mcintyre)
Neeleman, A., & Weerman, F. 1993. The balance between syntax and morphology. Natural Language and Linguistic Theory, 11, 433-475.
Olsen, S., 1998 (ed.) Semantische und konzeptuelle Aspekte der Partikelverbbildung mit ein-. T�bingen: Stauffenburg. Olsen, Susan. 2000. "Against Incorporation". In: Linguistische Arbeitsberichte 74.
Raffelsiefen, R., 1992. A Nonconfigurational Approach to Morphology. In: Aronoff, M., (ed.) Morphology Now. Albany: State University of New York Press.
Stechow, A. von (1996). The different readings of wieder "again". Journal of Semantics, 13, 87-138.
Stiebels, B., 1996. Lexikalische Argumente und Adjunkte. Berlin: Akademie.
Toivonen, I., 2001. The phrase structure of non-projecting words. Dissertation: Stanford.
Winkler, S, 1994. Secondary predication in English. Diss. T�bingen. (reworked as Focus and Secondary Predication. Berlin/ NY: de Gruyter, 1997)
Wurmbrand, S, 2000: "The structure(s) of particle verbs". Ms. Montr�al.
Zeller, J., 1997. How syntax restricts the lexicon: particles as thematic predicates. Ms. Frankfurt. To appear in Linguistische Berichte.
Zeller, J. 1999: Particle verbs, local domains, and a theory of lexical licensing. Dissertation, Frankfurt. (to appear as Particle Verbs and Local Domains. Amsterdam: John Benjamins)
Andrew McIntyre has a postdoctoral research and teaching position in the English department at the University of Leipzig, Germany. He has studied complex verb formation in German and English, and is interested in the semantics and argument structures of verbs.
|