Kasher, Asa, ed. (1998) Pragmatics: Critical Concepts, Vol. VI: Pragmatics, Grammar, Psychology, Sociology. Routledge, hardback, vi+559pp.
Reviewed by Zouhair Maalej, Department of English, University of Manouba-Tunis, Tunisia
[This is the second of a projected set of five reviews of the six volume set Pragmatics: Critical Concepts, edited by Asa Kasher. The first review, by Aldo Sevi, of volume IV appeared as <http://linguistlist.org/issues/12/12-2154.html> --Eds.]
Book's purpose and contents
The book is the last of a six-volume set to celebrate pragmatic concepts. It includes three parts reflecting linearly the items in the subtitle. Each part is preceded by a short introduction. All in all, twenty contributions from eminent pragmatists and less known ones spread unevenly over the three parts, with part twelve and fourteen each receiving four contributions and the bulk of papers going to the part on Pragmatics and Psychology. The critical section will reflect this division by offering three subsections in the critical section.
Part Twelve: Pragmatics and Grammar
93. Some Interactions of Syntax and Pragmatics, J. L. Morgan In this already published paper in Cole & Morgan (1975), Morgan, drawing on Ross's islandhood, shows strong interest in the fact that "grammar needn't be pragmatically transparent," (p. 17) which concern is continued later in Green & Morgan (1981).
94. Pragmatic Constraints on Linguistic Production, G. Gazdar Gazdar brings pragmatic constraints to bear on grammar. Some of the constraints include choice of expression, movement rules, deletion, morphology, and phonology.
95. Pragmatics and Grammatical Theory, Norbert Horstein Horstein's major argument is that the pair semantics-pragmatics contributes very little to Chomsky's competence since it does not enlighten us as to "what it is that people know about their native languages, how it is acquired and how it is put to use" (p. 54).
96. Applying Accessibility Theory, Mira Ariel Ariel argues that definite NPs are pragmatic candidates, and proposes to treat their contextual effects via Accessibility Theory (AT), which is termed as "a geographic view of context" and argued to supersede the notion of Givenness. Ariel isolates three types of context: General or Encylopedic Knowledge, Physical Environment of the speech event, and Linguistic Context, arguing that "natural languages code the degree of Accessibility of an antecedent, not its initial geographic source" (p. 63). This geographic view is soon abandoned in favour of the Parallel Distributed Processing (borrowed from McClelland & Rumelhart, 1986), which is a modular view of memory not in need of any geographic borderlines. The degree of Accessibility is a function of activation in memory, where the most accessible knowledge is that which is subject to higher activation and stored in short- term memory, with the least accessible having a lower level of activation and being retrievable from long-term memory. Some of the factors affecting accessibility include distance in discourse between an anaphor and its antecedent, competition between anaphors, saliency of an antecedent as a referent, and unity or change of frame. On the interaction between grammar and accessibility, Ariel claims that: (i) "Accessibility theory constrains possible grammaticalization processes involving pronominal forms," and (ii) AT "governs whatever optimal decisions are left by the grammar concerning sentential anaphora" (p. 77).
Part Thirteen: Pragmatics and Psychology
97. Responding to Indirect Speech Acts, Herbert H. Clark Clark brings to bear a psychological model on how listeners understand and respond to Indirect Speech Acts (ISAs). Properties of ISAs are multiplicity of meaning (as when a literal and conveyed meaning arise), logical priority of meaning (with primacy going to the conveyed meaning), rationality, conventionality (ISAs go by indirectly and idiomatically questioning someone about their ability), politeness (ISAs are motivated by politeness matters), purposefulness. Clark (p. 103) proposes three possible responses to isolate ISAs: expected responses, co-operative but unexpected responses, and uncooperative responses. Under expected responses are subsumed six properties (Clark promises 7 but gives 6 only): (i) multiplicity of moves (as deriving from multiplicity of meaning), (ii) functions of moves (preliminary, expected, and added moves), (iii) order of moves, (iv) selection of moves (as deriving from the logical priority of meaning), (v) politeness (where two- move responses are judged to be more polite), (vi) ellipsis (with an ISA and its response forming an adjacency pair). The response model offered consists in: answer alone, answer-plus- information, and information alone, and was checked in five experiments. Transparency was tested in relation to conventionality and idiomaticity. Clark postulates two kinds of information in understanding ISAs: (i) linguistic (relating to conventionality of means, conventionality of form, special markers of politeness, and transparency of indirect meaning) and (ii) functional (relating to the implausibility of the literal meaning and the speaker's imputed plans and goals).
98. Your Wish is My Command: Convention and Context in Interpreting Indirect Requests, Raymond W. Gibbs, Jr In a first experiment, Gibbs argues that conventionality enhances the interpretation of Indirect Requests (IRs), which have been elicited from subjects through real-world scenarios, by economising on processing time, but that conventional forms do not seem to be contextually interchangeable. In a second experiment, Gibbs asks subjects to rate the elicited IRs according to their appropriateness in the contexts in which they occur, and concludes that although "the notions of ^�convention of means' and ^�convention of form' are useful for discussing general patterns of conventionality in language, the conventionality of a particular utterance can only be measured given some specific social context" (p. 157). In a third experiment, time ratings for IRs in conventional contexts were found to be lower than those for non- conventional contexts.
99. Missing the Point. The Role of the Right Hemisphere in the Processing of Complex Linguistic Materials, Howard Gardner, Hiram H. Brownell, Wendy Wapner and Diane Michelow Gardner et al study right hemisphere patients (RHPs), who "appear to have difficulties in processing abstract sentences, in reasoning logically, and in maintaining a coherent stream of thought" (p. 172). To do so, they subject patients to narratives that they are expected to understand, recall, and retell. Story recall is scored on overall output, confusions, main events, confabulations, sequencing errors, and moral abstraction. The results of their study revolve around linguistic processing, narrative ability, and humour appreciation. In terms of linguistic processing, RHPs have been found to show qualitative difference recall, lack of ability to repeat segments in a condensed or abstract form, and flat delivery of narratives and answers to questions. With regard to narrative ability, results show that although RHPs perform well with spatial elements, they score low on emotional and non-canonical elements. Thus, incorrect emotional items are inappropriately embellished, but reasonably explained, which points to the fact that RHPs "can activate appropriate routines for inference, but tend to invoke them inappropriately" (p. 178). Reaction to non-canonical items is characterised by acceptance and even justification on the part of RHPs. Regarding humour appreciation, RHPs, like normals, reacted in the same way to humour, but find unfunny things funnier than the normals consider them. Attempting an explanation for these findings, Gardner et al explain that these defects hinge on "ideational or conceptual factors" rather than purely linguistic ones.
100. Appreciation of Pragmatic Interpretations of Indirect Commands: Comparison of Right and Left Hemisphere Brain-damaged Patients, Nancy S. Foldi While Clark and Gibbs studied indirect requests in normal people, Foldi studies indirect commands (ICs) in right and left hemisphere brain-damaged patients (RHBDPs and LHBDPs), with a control group from normal subjects. The reason for focusing on brain-damaged patients, explains Foldi, has to do with: (i) the fact that the polarization of language to the left hemisphere and of non-language functions to the right one has been under revision, (ii) the contradictory claims made about whether RHBDPs show deficits on pragmatic aspects of communication, and (iii) whether developmental literature shows dissociation between linguistic and pragmatic information. Indirect commands are matched to their direct counterparts, and show two individuals in a social setting appropriate for the content of ICs. Results for ICs reveal that while RHBDPs show preference for literal responses, LHBDPs and normals waver between the appropriate (more often) and literal ones, with the pragmatic responses receiving more prominence. Responses to direct commands, however, separated the brain- damaged patients (who are not consistent with their judgements) from the normals, who almost always choose the pragmatic not the literal responses. Foldi documents her results as being consistent with results arrived at by other workers with RHBDPs on narration and discourse abilities, in particular the appreciation of humour, idiomatic expressions, metaphor, indirect requests, and implicit attitudes. Foldi ends his paper by postulating three hypotheses to explain the performance of RHBDPs: (i) RHBDPs fail to appreciate the social relation between participants in a given exchange and the intonational contour that realises it, (ii) although this hypothesis was not borne out and as research in indirect acts in general demonstrates, RHBDPs seem, like children, to attend to non-salient dimensions of communication (i.e. "valued the physically verifiable aspects of a similar two-person exchange, even though those aspects had nothing to do with the intent or content of the communication" (p. 210), and (iii) RHBDPs fail "to integrate the necessary components of information in order to arrive at a felicitous indirect interpretation" (p. 210).
101. Pragmatics and Aphasia, Ruth Lesser and Lesley Milroy Lesser & Milroy point to some of the problems posed by the Boston Diagnostic Aphasia Examination used by many researchers on aphasia such as confusing linguistic processing abilities (such as calculating sense relations between lexical items or sense properties of sentences) and inferencing abilities (such as the capacity to infer implicatures), which amounts to the distinction between "linguistic meaning" and "speaker meaning." The bulk of the paper is devoted to repair strategies used by aphasics in and out of clinical contexts.
102. Pragmatics and the Modularity of Mind, Asa Kasher In this article reprinted from Davis (1991), Kasher seeks to justify modular pragmatics. Kasher hypothesises that the modular approach to the study of the mind includes (i) faculties having various degrees of independence and access to propositional content in a certain domain, (ii) mental mechanisms, with memory as one example, (iii) cognitive modules (in Fodor's sense), which are domain-specific, primary, computationally autonomous, and innately specified, and (iv) central cognitive systems which are "neither domain-specific nor informationally encapsulated, but related to "general mental capacities of belief formation and problem solving." Deixis presupposes the existence of a perceptual module and a linguistic module, with resolution as pertaining to the central cognitive systems. Lexical pragmatic presuppositions are "beyond the power of cognitive modules" (p. 241). With regard to ISAs, Kasher invokes the presumption of literalness as facilitated by the linguistic modules (syntactic and semantic properties of lexical items), thus turning attention away from the hemispheres of the brain to the modularity of the mind. Implicatures, on the other hand, are monitored by a principle of rationality, claiming that even Sperber & Wilson's relevance theory is built on rational principles. Kasher concludes by positing three parts to core pragmatics: (1) "a pragmatic, purely linguistic competence, embodying ... knowledge of certain speech act verbs," (2) "a pragmatic, non-linguistic competence, governing aspects of intentional action in general, including linguistic activity, which is intentional in nature," and (3) "a class of various interface features
103. The Ontogenesis of Speech Acts, Jerome S. Bruner In this 1975 essay, Bruner imputes the distortion in language acquisition (LA) research to a preoccupation with syntax at the expense of language use. Bruner, however, suggests that not only is structure not unimportant for LA but, most importantly, not "totally arbitrary" (p. 255-6) in that the structure of language tends to correlate with the psychological events that it encodes. To illustrate, he invokes the subject-predicate as correlating with topic-comment and case grammar as correlating with "the structure of human action in infancy" (p. 258). Some of the processes that facilitate the learning of communicative devices that encode the concepts of agent, action, recipient include: (i) learning segments from interaction with the mother, (ii) elaborate construction of inter- subjective routines, (iii) the routine attend to ? act upon, and (iv) prosodic patterns. However, Bruner insists that play is a determinative factor that leads the child to elaborate communication rules.
104. The Acquisition of Performatives Prior to Speech, Elizabeth Bates, Luigia Camaioni and Virginia Volterra In this 1975 essay, Bates et al are interested in the cognitive and social developments of communication in children, arguing that the acquisition of performative structures at the prelinguistic level originates in gesture, eye contact, and prelinguistic vocalizations. Bates et al explain the use of prelinguistic imperative as a way of using the adult "as a means to a desired object" (p. 278), whereas prelinguistic declarative is the use of an object as a way of attracting the adult's attention through pointing, showing, or giving. Adducing evidence from case studies with Italian infants, Bates et al suggest that children prelinguistically engage in communication with adults in three phases: (i) the perlocutionary phase, (ii) the illocutionary phase, and (iii) the locutionary phase.
105. The Meaning of Children's First Words: Evidence from the Input, Anat Ninio, Postscript (1995) Ninio suggests that children map one- word utterances onto "any other piece of human behavior they observe" (p. 299), suggesting that children attribute intentional communicative dimensions to one-word utterances. In a case study of mother-child interaction, Ninio concludes that "one-word utterances are lexical realizations of complex communicative acts" (310). In a Postscript, Ninio mentions a follow up study undertaken in 1992, where past findings arrived at have been corroborated.
106. The Pragmatics of Formulas in L2 Learner Speech: Use and Development, Jens Bahs, Harmut Burmeister and Thomas Vogel Bahs et al study formulaic speech among L2 Learners as enhancing pragmatic abilities. After expressing their dissatisfaction with current classifications of formulaic expressions, Bahs et al distinguish: expressive, directive, game or play, polyfunctional, question, and phatic formulas.
107. Disturbance of Pragmatic Functioning, Benita Rae Smith and Esva Leinonen Smith & Leinonen offer a review of the literature on children suffering from pragmatic impediments to comprehension and expression, known as semantic-pragmatic disorders.
108. Pragmatics and Cognition in Treatment of Language Disorders (Revised), G. Albyn Davis The paper by Davis is one of the few that is updated and includes recent references. Davis studies the role of pragmatics in cases of aphasia. Davis isolates three types of context in connection with aphasia: linguistic, paralinguistic, and extralinguistic. Davis envisages a treatment hierarchy, including knowledge (of the world), props (real objects instead of pictures, although real objects did not make much difference), interaction (natural conversation with turn-taking structure), purpose/situation (role- playing activities), people (family members and friends participating in clinical activities), and settings (simulated world in clinics and hospitals).
Part Fourteen: Pragmatics and Sociology
109. Felicity's Condition, Erving Goffman Goffman proposes to study what he calls "social presuppositions in language use" (p. 396). This is a broader view of presupposition than the ones known in the pragmatics literature. Social presuppositions range from "everything that gets said early in a conversation can be presupposed in some way by later utterances in it" (p. 407), which amounts to anaphora, to "what each speaker presupposes his listeners knew about the world and its working before the conversational forgathering itself occurred" (p. 410), which amounts to social experience with knowledge .
110. Political Determinants of Pragmatic and Sociolinguistic Choices (Revised), Hartmut Haberland and Tove Skutnabb-Kangas Haberland & Skutnabb-Kangas address the more political problem of how political contexts in a given society impact how scientific knowledge is interpreted and applied. In a Postscript (1995), the authors mention that their original paper has been shortened by almost one half.
111. The Tact Maxim, Geoffrey N. Leech Leech correlates Searle's illocutionary categories of directives and commissives to Competitive (discourteous negative politeness) and Convivial (courteous positive politeness) functions. The Tact Maxim (TM) tends to be inversely proportional to the degree of linguistic directness, i.e. the more an illocution is indirect, the more polite it is. Indirect illocutions tend to be more polite as they (i) increase the degree of optionality for not doing something, and (ii) diminish force. The TM has two dimensions to it: (a) negative: Minimise the cost to h, and (b) positive: Maximise the benefit to h (e.g. making an offer to h). Leech isolates three pragmatic scales: (a) cost-benefit scale, (b) optionality scale, and (c) indirectness scale.
112. Politeness, Introduction to the Reissue: A Review of Recent Work, Penelope Brown and Stephen C. Levinson Brown & Levinson argue that a great part of the mismatch between the pragmatic dichotomy of the said and implicated phenomena owes its existence to politeness phenomena. Critical of Leech's Politeness principle as a parallel to Grice's Co-operative Principle, they hold that politeness depends on face (individuals self- esteem), isolating three main strategies: (a) positive politeness (the desire to be approved), (b) negative politeness (the desire to be unimpeded in one's actions), and (c) off-record politeness (avoidance of equivocal impositions). Owing to counterexamples from non-European cultures (Samoans and Ilongots), Brown & Levinson express reservations vis-�-vis Grice's theory of intentional communication (for conceptual, psychological, and cultural reasons) and speech act theory (for its sentential bias). Three sociological factors determine the level of politeness: (a) power, (b) distance, and (c) ranking. A recurrent concept on which face depends is culture, which seems to challenge any claim for universal models of politeness.
Appendix: Papers and Books This small section includes further references to the topics dealt with in the book, most of which are new ones.
Critical evaluation As part of a six-volume set, the current volume looks more like a reader in pragmatics as it includes some well known already published papers and book chapters in the pragmatics literature. Although very little in the way of new insight is on offer (in all volumes judging by their table of contents), this compilation is essential background reading for students of pragmatics and new researchers in the pragmatics of language. Particular to this volume under review, bringing together papers that directly and indirectly relate to the pragmatics of language is, to say the least, a laudable enterprise for which Kasher is to be commended.
1. The papers of Part Twelve (Pragmatics and Grammar) owe their value not so much to any new/original claims they make, but to the issues they raise such as the autonomy of syntax and the modularity of mind, which are classic bones of contention between formal and functional/cognitive schools of linguistics. In claiming that "grammar needn't be pragmatically transparent," Morgan seems to be acting on the assumption that the linguistic sign is necessarily arbitrary, and, by extension, grammar is not symbolic. In the cognitive quarter, Langacker (1987: 12), arguing against the hegemony of Saussure's l'arbitraire du signe, claims that the cognitive conception of language as symbolic should be extended "beyond lexicon to grammar." In contradistinction to Morgan, Gazdar's defence of pragmatic constraints on grammar is more commonsensical. This was addressed as the pragmatics of grammar by Hindelang (1981). Horstein's assumption that native speakers can make well-formedness judgements (performance) about sentence structures (competence) in UG terminology amounts to confusing the linguist with the native. His argument that pragmatics does not contribute much to Chomsky's approach to language amounts to asking whether Chomsky's competence/ performance distinction explains how language is acquired and used, which we know formal linguists are not primarily concerned with. Pragmatics is not "about" language, but studies language in use. "How it is acquired" is partly taken care of by the sub- discipline of psycholinguistics, and "how it is put to use" is in part the concern of cognitive psychology (Bower & Cirilo, 1985: 71). Clearly, by asking of pragmatics more than its theoretical programme can accommodate, Horstein wants it to be a jack of all trades. Broadening the scope of pragmatics to dealing with NPs, Ariel seems to suggest that an important portion of grammar, namely, indexicals (including pronouns and spatio-temporal deictic expressions) and NPs (including definite descriptions, proper names, demonstrative expressions, etc.) is the epitome of a pragmatically transparent grammar. Judging, then, from this small set of papers, the interaction between grammar and pragmatics is supported by all, with Morgan showing more reservation and caution.
2. The papers of Part Thirteen (Pragmatics and Psychology) are more original. Clark and Gibbs papers overlap in that both deal with the role of conventionality in the interpretation of ISAs. Although Clark's recorded ISAs may be argued to commend more genuinely reliable results than Gibbs's elicited IRs (which is generally the very criticism addressed to the lab practices of cognitive psychologists), Gibbs does not see the resolution of IRs with the same eye as Clark. While Clark's discussion of ISAs raises the age-old dichotomy of literal (as a property of sentences, i.e. semantics) vs. non- literal meaning (as a property of utterances or speaker's conveyed meaning), Gibbs argues that IRs "lie on a continuum between highly conventional and non-conventional utterances" but not on "whether the utterance is literal or metaphoric" (p. 163), which Kasher (this volume) strongly contests as not realistic in the case of neuropsychological research. In the same line of thought, Kasher (1991: 395) rightly argues that "there is no reason to assume that in understanding metaphorical expressions we employ the same principles that identify for us the ^�higher' intended end of an ^�indirect speech act'." Kasher (this volume) resolves the issue of ISAs "in terms of presumed, literal forces, as determined by a linguistic module on grounds of strictly linguistic information, and of eventual forces, as determined by some central device on grounds of the presumed, literal forces as well as additional non-linguistic information" (p. 244), which not only throws us back into the literal vs. non-literal dichotomy, but also counts as an implicit acknowledgement of two different mental "locations" for purely linguistic (cognitive module) and pragmatic information (central cognitive system).
Gardner et al and Foldi's papers are a rehabilitation of the right hemisphere in language processing. Evidence from neuropsychology corroborates this. For instance, Corina (1999), for instance, argues that right hemisphere disorders, which were thought to occasion no damage to language skills, have been shown to be responsible for the disruption of the meta-control of language and discourse abilities in both speakers and signers (Maalej, forthcoming 2001). One may safely infer from Gardner et al's paper that pragmatic knowledge is right hemisphere-dependent as RHPs have difficulty recounting coherent stories told to them and appreciating to their just value non-canonical items. Foldi offers evidence to the effect that RHBDPs fail to bring pragmatic appreciation to bear on linguistic material. It is now common knowledge that such deficiencies observed in RHPs attest to two separate linguistic and pragmatic modules in the left and right hemispheres, respectively. Further evidence may be adduced. Studying dementia in Alzheimer patients, Keller & Rech (1998: 315) pointed out that these patients show one largely preserved cognitive capacity for phonological, morphological and syntactic items but disturbed discourse-processing and semantic abilities, and argued for the same conclusion on the provision for separate modules for linguistic and pragmatic competencies. Further, Campbell (1999: 63) argues that the capacity for speechreading is impaired after left-hemisphere lesion (affecting supramarginal speech processing), and rates higher in the perception of faces and visual movements, showing that "audiovisual speech and silent speechreading do not seem to lateralize to the left hemisphere as cleanly as does heard speech." In contrast to all this evidence, Kasher (1991a) argues for a "Modular Pragmatics in the Left Hemisphere Hypothesis." The findings of Gardner et al definitely battle against Kasher's hypothesis (although it is acknowledged that "parts of central pragmatics are in the right hemisphere," p. 396): If it were true that linguistic and pragmatic items were monitored in the same hemisphere, RHPs would have no such impairment that Gardner et al and Foldi find them suffering from.
In essays 103-105, the psycholinguistics of acquisition (prelinguistic, linguistic, and pragmatic) is addressed. Bruner and Bates et al address the prelinguistic predisposition to communicate in children. While Bruner situates it mostly in mother-child interaction in play, Bates et al fit it into performative structures. In contradistinction, Ninio's paper addresses the pragmatics of first word acquisition as a form of lexicalisation of communicative acts, arguing that children attribute intentional communicative meanings to one-word utterances, which implies that illocutions are present at this phase of language development. Rae Smith & Leinonen offer to study pragmatic impediments to comprehension and expression, but end up giving a review of the literature on the topic without a real contribution to the subject. The essay by Davis presents aphasic people as suffering from pragmatic deficiencies, knowing that aphasia is a left-hemisphere impairment and pragmatics is right-hemisphere dependent.
3. The papers of Part Fourteen (Pragmatics and Sociology) If Goffman's paper on presupposition suffers from displacement by being transported into the social area (he calls his theme "social presupposition"), that of Haberland & Skutnabb-Kangas has very little to do with pragmatics altogether as they themselves rightly asked the question: "One might ask what this paper has to do with pragmatics." The truncated version massacred the import of the original I happen to have read before.
To conclude this review, a few general remarks about editing are in good order:
(i) If not for the dates of the references in the essays, not acknowledging for all essays that they have already been published elsewhere is misleading for non-specialists in the field (e.g. students). [Sevi also made this point in his review of Vol. 4 --Eds]
(ii) Some of the papers having been actually book chapters elsewhere, the volume suffers from formatting errors and pragmatic displacement of deixis. For instance, in Ariel's chapter there is a subsection 0.2.1. but not 0.2.2., then 0.4.2., without 0.4.1. "This book" (p. 76) refers to her book, Accessing Noun-phrase Antecedents, from which the chapter has been taken. "In previous chapters" sows the same confusion (p. 77). In Leech's chapter (p. 462), the first paragraph includes reference to "this and the next chapter," where "this" refers to the chapter in Kasher's book, but "next" to Leech's Principles of Pragmatics from which the chapter has been taken. Another occurrence of "this" in "this book" (p. 472) introduces the same confusion between Leech's and Kasher's respective books. Cognitively and pragmatically, such imperfections have slowed down the pace of my reading of the book while reviewing it, and proved to be costly in terms of the resolution of deixis and ambiguity. The same thing occurs in Lesser & Milroy, whose first sentence reads: "We have devoted some space to this selective review of Grice's ideas ..." (p. 217), where "this" may shock the reader as having read no review. It is only a few lines later that the reader realises that this chapter is taken from a full- length book by the authors (Linguistics and Aphasia). In the same paper, reference is made to the utterances in (38) and (39) (p. 220), which do not figure in the paper. In Brown & Levinson's essay, "this" (p. 488) in "this work" and "this" (p. 492) in "this book" both refer to Politeness. Some Universals in Language Use, but not to Kasher's book.
(iii) The running title in the header of the page includes the chapter heading and not the essay title, which does not help browsing through the volume for the different essays.
(iv) The inclusion of papers under a heading in which they do not logically fit is quite common in these volumes. For instance, indirect speech acts figure in two different volumes: four essays on ISAs (71-74) in Volume IV devoted to presupposition, and four essays on ISAs (97-100) in Volume VI under review. It would have been better to include the ones in Volume IV in volume VI, as there is a rationale for including them there with the other essays on ISAs. This is not an isolated anomaly. Browsing through the table of contents of Volume I and volume III, I noticed that Bar-Hillel's "Indexical Expressions" features in Volume I but not in Volume III, whose title is Indexicals and Reference. Goffman's paper, which treats "social presupposition," is in the company of two papers on politeness (by Leech and Brown & Levinson) instead of being in Volume IV, devoted to presupposition.
References Bower, Gordon H. & Randolph K. Cirilo (1985). "Cognitive Psychology and Text Processing." In: Teun A. Van Dijk (ed.), Handbook of Discourse Analysis (Vol. 1). Disciplines of Discourse. London/New York: Academic Press, 71- 105.
Campbell, Ruth (1999). "Language from Faces: Uses of the Face in Speech and in Sign." In: Lynn Messing & Ruth Campbell (eds.), 57- 73.
Corina, David P. (1999). "Neural Disorders of Language and Movements: Evidence from American Sign Language." In: Lynn Messing & Ruth Campbell (eds.), 27-43.
Green, Georgia M. & J. L. Morgan (1981). "Pragmatics, Grammar, and Discourse." In: P. Cole (ed.), Radical Pragmatics. London/New York: Academic Press. 167-181.
Hindelang, G�tz (1981). "Pragmatical Grammar and the Pragmatics of Grammar." In: H. Parret, M. Sbisa & J. Verschueren (eds.), Possibilities and Limitations of Pragmatics. Amsterdam: J. Benjamins B. V., 331-342.
Kasher, Asa (1991). "On the Pragmatic Modules: A Lecture." Journal of Pragmatics 16,381-397.
Keller, J�rg & Trixi Rech (1998). "Towards a Modular Description of the Deficits in Spontaneous Speech in Dementia." Journal of Pragmatics 29, 313-332.
Langacker, Ronald W. (1987). Foundations of Cognitive Grammar Vol.1). Theoretical Prerequisites. Stanford: Stanford University Press.
Maalej, Zouhair. "Review of Lynn Messing & Ruth Campbell (eds.), Gesture, Speech and Sign. Oxford: Oxford University Press (1999). To appear in the journal of Sign Language Studies (Fall 2001).
McClelland, J. L. & D. E. Rumelhart. eds) (1986). Parallel Distributed Processing (two volumes). Cambridge: MIT Press.
Messing, Lynn & Ruth Campbell (eds.) 1999). Gesture, Speech and Sign. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Morgan, J. L. (1975). "Some Interactions of Syntax and Pragmatics." In: P. Cole & J. L.Morgan (eds.), Syntax and Semantics (vol. 3) Speech Acts. New York/London: Academic Press, 289-303.
Morgan, J. L. (1978). "Two Types of Convention in Indirect Speech A." In: P. Cole (ed.), Syntax and Semantics (vol. 9). Pragmatics. London/New York: Academic Press, 261-279.
About the reviewer The reviewer is an assistant professor of linguistics. His interests include cognitive linguistics, metaphor, pragmatics, cognition-culture interface, critical discourse analysis, sign language and gesture, etc.
|