Allan, Keith (2001) Natural Language Semantics. Blackwell Publishers, xix+529pp, hardback ISBN 0-631-19296-4, $64.95.
Reviewed by Eleni Koutsomitopoulou, ABD Computational Linguistics Georgetown University
Another review of this book can be found at http://linguistlist.org/issues/12/12-1709.html
OVERVIEW Allan's "Natural Language Semantics" is an introductory book on semantics and as such its "intended readership is undergraduate and graduate students of linguistics and relevant areas of psychology, philosophy, anthropology, sociology, communications, language studies, and education." The book indeed discusses "fundamental concepts for linguistic semantics." What makes it special is the author's encompassing consideration that meaning is "cognitively and functionally motivated." even though the tools for its description are formal. The author's main goal is to offer his intended readership the basic tools and skills needed in order to exercise proper and linguistically acceptable semantic analysis. To this aim, Allan takes pains with his presentation of varied linguistic methods of semantic analysis. The traditional formalist approach has been elucidated in as great depth and clarity as the cognitive and functionalist approach.
Each chapter includes a standard "Where we are heading" introductory part, as well as a "Summary" section and "Notes on further reading". Throughout a chapter the reader will find exercises, the answers of which readers may find online at: http://www.arts.monash.edu.au/ling/nls/getans.shtml This user- friendly layout as well as the presence of a section explaining the "Symbols and Conventions" used in the book and the quite comprehensive Index makes this book a very accessible textbook for both undergraduate and general graduate work on semantics.
Each of the 13 chapters may be considered fairly autonomous. Below I will present the contents of each chapter along with my critical comments on certain theoretical practices and views adopted and presented in each chapter. In closing, I will proceed into a short general critical evaluation of the book.
In Chapter 1 Allan describes basic semantic concepts such as the metalanguage of semantic theory, inference, the nature of speech events, context, the principles of cooperation and relevance, and compositionality. These concepts are presented informally and non-technically by way of introduction and they are interwoven around the epicenter of such fundamental and elementary notions as that of a metalanguage for semantic analysis and context. The author presents some criteria for the selection of a metalanguage appropriate for semantic analysis. It is pointed that a metalanguage is an expressive and comprehensive formal language that ideally possesses the same descriptive and explanatory power as natural language. Some further assumptions about semantic theory and the interdependence between semantics and the other levels of linguistic analysis are also informally discussed in this chapter. Context is defined as "a model of the world and time spoken or written of", or the discourse model or discourse world, but also as a "co-text", i.e. the discourse preceding and following a given linguistic point in discourse. Context is also meant as the pragmatic "situation of utterance" and "situation of interpretation" corresponding to the factors of place and time of the speaker and the "hearer" respectively during the utterance. Other general assumptions about semantics and meaning in human languages are also discussed in this chapter. Because of its informal style this first chapter offers an excellent opportunity for students in undergraduate classes to exercise their written and oral argumentation skills. The summary section recapitulates the main concepts and new terms discussed in the chapter. The summary along with the extensive references to related literature in the "notes on further reading" make the first chapter a comprehensive introduction to semantics for both beginners and more advanced linguistics students.
Chapter 2 starts with a crucial trifold differentiation between sentence meaning, utterance meaning and speaker meaning. Then the focus shifts to an informal description of extension and intension, reference and anaphora. The latter are brought up by way of explanation of the distinction between "dictionary meanings" and meanings of utterances in the discourse model or discourse world. The reference to "dictionary meaning" is merely lexicographic and the author does not offer a much-needed linguistic criticism of the lexicographic practices followed regarding homonymous and polysemous terms (but see next chapter for further discussion of homonyms). Thus he uses a rather problematic example from Webster's New Collegiate Dictionary 1977 to demonstrate homonymy and polysemy. The term "canine" is separated in two "homonyms" canine1 and canine2 that basically differ in part of speech identity rather than in meaning. The noun "canine" bears two quite distinct senses that in a different dictionary could have been cataloged as homonyms themselves. No comments on the fuzziness of the example (and the related lexicographic practices) have been made by the author. A more obvious example of homonymy and polysemy would have better served the purposes of this section. Leaving the details of the lexicon for the next chapter, chapter 2 builds on the notion of "world and the time spoken of" that was presented in the previous chapter. First, speaker's meaning is defined as the speaker's intended meaning of an utterance. Utterance meaning is defined as the meaning of an utterance as it is perceived by a hearer in the context of its utterance. Sentence meaning is defined as the informative content of a sentence expressed in terms of an abstract system. The next step is what is noted as an informal description of the terms "denotation", "extension", "intension" and "reference". Also, the term "proposition" is used in this chapter for the first time. The final sections of the second chapter get into the specifics of generic NPs and anaphora. This chapter is packed with technical terms and sophisticated concepts, and the author's attempt to define each and every one of them so early in the book and in the same chapter leaves the reader with the impression that they were intended to be "brushed away" rather than studied in depth.
Chapter 3 focuses on the lexicon and its basic structure. Words within the lexicon are designated "listemes". In the same chapter, the lexicon is seen as part of a bigger construction that of the encyclopedia. Basic differences between the lexicon and the encyclopedia are outlined, the most highlighted being the distinction between meaning and denotation. The perspective adopted in this chapter is that lexicography is the construction of "models of the mental lexicon". In this line of thought, the author points out Lyons's 1977 suggestion that lexical entries have been assigned indices for easy access during the formal, morphosyntactic and semantic specification of an entry. Allan then goes as far as to discuss Jackendoff's 1995 and 1997 lexical licensing theory and explain its significance in justifying traditional lexicographic practices that distinguish for instance the word "canine" in two homonyms given only their morphosyntactic specification, or part-of-speech information: "member of the dog family (N)" vs. "pertaining to the dog family (Adj)". The gist of this presentation is the important lesson that each lexical entry is a complex network of relations between formal (i.e. pertaining to form), morphosyntactic and semantic specifications, i.e. we derive semantic information for an entry from both its form and its part-of-speech information, and conversely we discover the appropriate form and part-of-speech of a lexical entry given the intended meaning. Another interesting point in the 3rd chapter was made about proper names. These are taken to be partly or wholly defined in the lexicon where form features like spellings and pronunciation as well as gender are thoroughly specified and from which speakers of a language draw upon when baptizing new members of a community.
Chapter 4 touches upon morphology and its connection to meaning and semantics. The issue of "polyword listemes", i.e. compounds, idioms and phrasal verbs, and their seeming non-compositionality is being explored. Listemes are described morphologically and in relation to each other. English inflection (affixes) and nonderived lexemes are listemes in the lexicon. Languages with richer morphology may follow different rules. The general rule is that if the meaning of an inflectional/derived listeme is transparent (compositional) then it should exist in the lexicon as two separate listemes (affix and root). Derived lexemes (including lexemes that are products of zero-derivation) present different cases in that they usually are independent from their "derivational origins", which makes them good lexical entries. Phrasal verbs are compounds (often discontinuous) and as such are listemes. Idioms, even "polyword" ones, are lexemes of a certain morphosyntactic class. For instance, nominal idioms are likened to NPs. Sound symbolism is the phenomenon in natural languages during which, through certain lexemes, a conventional (thus language- specific), yet arbitrary, connection between the form and the meaning is adopted. A typical example of sound symbolism are onomatopoetic words that mimic sounds of the denotatum. Allan presents three different types of sound symbolism: phonesthesia, synesthesia and ideophones, and he suggests --for a good reason-- that synesthetic words do not belong in the lexicon. This chapter is rich in examples from English and other languages when it describes sound symbolism, but it lacks a similar crosslinguistic depth when it accounted for compounds and their presence in the lexicon.
Chapter 5 delves into connotation and jargon. The author bridges the two by regarding connotation as "what is being naturally believed about the meaning of a word" and jargon as the "realization of the special meanings of the language of a group". Connotation is seen as a source of inspiration for the creation of new vocabulary. Connotation is what differentiates synonyms in certain context in such a way that no two words can substitute each other entirely and in every context in natural languages (this is what Allan has earlier baptized as the "blocking principle"). Subtle connotations of names and terms of address follow different styles of naming and addressing, and different languages exploit this source in various ways. (see Joos 1961 for style in English). At this point, Allan explains the connotations of discriminatory language expressed with "-IST dysphemisms", and other newly enlisted listemes. He then describes "taboo" words and the generation of substitute euphemistic words or expressions. He also explains "pejorization" or negative connotations and their societal persecutions. When he discusses gender-specific language ("words denoting women") and how it is pejorized, he calls forth the issue of polysemous words with taboo senses and how natural language users resort to semantic narrowing to eliminate the taboo senses. On the same topic, dysphemisms are used to show the speaker's disapproval and often separate the Speaker's (and his/her audience's) opinion from that of the opponent. Insults are analyzed in detail and Allan offers five types of "dysphemistic terms of insult". The cognitive- functional attitude of the author is becoming apparent when he reminds us that euphemisms and dysphemisms promote semantic change. Other ways for language to evolve semantically are: remodelling, phonetic similarity, acronyms, abbreviations, verbal play, circumlocution, hyperbole, understatement, metonymy, substitution, synecdoche, borrowing. A big absent here is metaphor, however, the author categorizes metaphor ("metaphorical extension") along with "lexical confusion" and "semantic transfer" as semantic processes rather than linguistic realities. These processes are responsible for bringing about new listemes or new meanings to existing listemes. Next, Allan focuses on jargon. Jargon is often associated with specialized vocabulary, special syntactic forms, and special typographical or other norms. Its main function is to serve as a technical language or the language of a specialist. The second function is to promote group consciousness between people who share similar interests and use the jargon. Like the groups they represent, jargons can be highly prestigious. Allan also explains how jargons have taken a bad name: they often only serve the image of the group they represent with no real or substantial need for a specialized language. Even "social chit-chat" is a type of jargon. Jargons in a language may become quite elaborated to the point of displaying discrete styles.
Intersentential semantics is investigated in Chapter 6. After a brief sketch of propositional calculus, the author discusses conventional and conversational implicatures, presuppositions, and illocutions. The basic tools for truth-conditional semantic analysis are presented here in their most elementary form. However, the author is -- justifiably -- guided by the belief that natural language is less than a ideal subject for truth- condition analysis: implicature, especially as it comes up in discourse (conversational implicature) is very important when we account for natural language meaning. Related terms like implication, entailment, and conventional implicature are being examined. Also, semantic presupposition and pragmatic presupposition are examined in this chapter, especially in regard to conversational implicature. Interesting points in this chapter are also the use of truth- conditional or formal semantics in general to elucidate differences between entailment and synonymy, as well as conventional vs. conversational implicature. For instance, entailment is regarded as semantic implication, and synonymy as semantic equivalence, whereas conventional implicature is a non- truth conditional semantic implication that is a lexical rather than propositional assignment and part of the linguistic system rather than the speaker or listener and their language expectations and regardless of whether we flout or observe the cooperative principle or the maxims.
An example of conventional implicature is the two aspects of the maxim of Quantity: there is a maximum quantity with a negative implicature, and a minimum interpreted quantity, and the clues for each one are either lexical or grammatical. The issue of presuppositions and their defeasibility is analyzed next. In sum, Allan defends the following position: The fact that presupposition can be made void renders them pragmatic or at least at the borders of the semantic with the pragmatic realm. Although both a proposition A and its negation should entail B in order for B to be a presupposition, the linguistic reality of "presupposition negation" undermines the semantic nature of presupposition itself: a presupposition negation negates the presupposition proposition as well as the presupposition behind it. When the presupposition is negated but not the presupposition proposition that sustains it, the proposition becomes underspecified or indeterminable (neither true or false). In illocutions, presuppositions are those "preconditions" (or "preparatory conditions" in Allan's terms) that help speaker and listener communicate felicitously. Since preconditions, and therefore presupposition, are subject to the maxim of quality, both are part of conversational implicatures. Accepting presuppositions as conversational rather than conventional implicatures would explain the defeasibility of presupposition.
Traditional formal semantics starts with Chapter 7, where the author presents predicate logic, set theory, functions, and the lambda operator. A simple proposition and its constituents are analyzed semantically using formal tools. Ways for the semantic analysis of clauses and sentences are also reviewed. The notion of "scope" of quantifiers and operators is first presented here. The set theory is linked to certain lexical relations as "hyponym of" ("subset of") and "hypernym of" or "superordinate of" ("superset of"). The interpretation and assignment functions are being explained and distinguished: assignment is mechanical and enables the proposition with its predicates and arguments to be evaluated for truth, whereas interpretation defines the conditions for the satisfaction of a predicate for a specific domain. An interesting methodological stance of the author becomes clear in this chapter: the author chooses to use the lambda operator in this book only as a "convenient extension to predicate calculus", instead of delving into the advanced issues of its use in model theoretic semantics by type categorial languages (languages that only use two types: t for truth value and e for entity to define every other type.)
Chapter 8 makes a leap from formal to cognitive and lexical semantics and the concepts of scripts, frames and semantic fields. The notion of compositionality is revisited in light of "componential analysis" and the search for "semantic primitives". A more formal definition of "listeme meaning" is given in this chapter. The most prevailing cognitive trademark in this chapter is Allan's view of semantic properties (the equivalent of "features" in formalistic approaches to semantic analysis) and semantic relation among entities: Allan points out that both properties of entities and relations among entities are greatly constrained by the perceptual categories and relations that the speakers have internalized. Thus, intensions and their extensions in space and time are critical for any account of senses and sense relations. Following is a basic differentiation between scritps, frames and fields as explicated by Allan: Scripts apply to text in order to fill in the gaps of the textual description of dynamic event structures. The speaker assumes a lot of details that s/he knows that the Hearer can deduce from their own internalized knowledge of scripts. Frames apply to listemes in order to determine essential characteristics (attributes and functions) of their denotata. Frames encompass all the relevant "arguments" of a listeme (in fact, of its denotatum). Frames can be formalized if we think of them as grids with certain predefined slots that get their values (i.e. morphosyntactic and semantic information) once they apply to specific listemes. Certain selectional restrictions may apply, but the task of identifying a full set of them is regarded by Allan as "impracticable and at worst impossible." In an attempt to reconcile lexical and generative semantic approaches, Allan at this point acknowledges Pustejovsky's work (e.g. 1995) on using frames as the basis for the "co-occurrence constraint" when building the lexical semantic structures of a generative lexicon. Semantic fields refer to certain listemes and are defined by the conceptual field in which the denotatum of the specific listeme occurs. Conceptual fields are said to be in the same semantic field if the listemes corresponding to each denotatum in this field are semantically related (e.g. if the different denotata bear certain similarities). This notion of conceptual field (vs. the notion of semantic field) as presented here seems to be on more of Allan's elaborated reconciliatory attempts to bridge the gap between lexical and conceptual semantics on one hand, and abstract semantic structures on the other. An example of a semantic field encompassing different conceptual fields in different languages is discussed: color. Some elementary semantic concepts are now revisited in light of the notion of scripts, frames and fields: hyponymy (Chaffin 1992), antonymy, and meronymy. The focus then shifts into componential analysis (Wilkins 1668) and a reminder of older "contrastive and distributional" analyses (Harris 1951) in phonology and morphology. And right when we thought that we had dispensed with "semantic primitives", Allan comes back to this notion in the frame of "compositional semantic analysis". Theories of J. Katz (e.g. 1972), Weinreich (1966) and Wierzbicka (1980) are presented and criticized as attempts for a valid semantic metalanguage.
After the introduction to cognitive semantics in Ch. 8, Chapter 9 presents some case-studies traditionally explored by cognitive semanticists: the meanings of "back", colors, and classifiers. It becomes clear that semantic categories are essentially experiential: for instance, the way humans perceive the human body (anatomically and physiologically) affects their cognitive model for extensions of meaning of "back" to animate and inanimate objects, spatial uses of time, direction and space attributes, etc. Similarly, the way we see and categorize what we see affects our way of naming and categorizing colors (MacLaury 1997, but also E. Rosch 1978 et seq.). Semantic (lexical) categories are constructed in terms of "vantages", windows of perception we select to pay attention to and in which similarity and difference are being balanced or measured against a steady factor (a fixed point of reference). Vantage theory starts with "natural" categories and accounts for their perception, their extensions and mappings into more synthetic classes: red, green, blue are basic natural color categories, but, say, purple is not, and the question for Vantage theory (and most of cognitive linguistic theory) is how humans come to linguistically categorize complex (i.e. composed of other elementary) entities. Vantage theory is not an innovation, although Allan presents and analyzes it at length: it's rather a sum up of older theories of experiential subcategorization starting with Eleanor Rosch (or even before Rosch, the Sapir-Whorf hypothesis). This chapter quickly reviews the long-standing dispute on "linguistic relativity". Classifiers are examined in light of linguistic relativity and semantic crosslinguistic universalia. Even though all the world's languages seem to adopt the same eight general groups of classifiers for entity classification Allan proposes (material make-up, function, shape, consistency, size, location, arrangement and quanta), each one may choose in specific occasions to focus on different salient features (attributes) of the referent as perceived in various time and space coordinates. Allan often uses the term "typical denotatum" denoting exactly the use of exemplars in prototype semantics for recognition and (sub)categorization.
Chapter 10 is a glimpse at prototype semantics touching upon topics like the "typical denotatum", "gestalten", (cognitive linguistic) stereotypes, intension and the intended referent. Allan criticizes the prototype theory making a good point about its low representational power. Emphasis on prototypes, Allan says, does make respectable the correlation of semantics with cognitive processes, but -- and this is his main point of criticism -- prototype semantics does not reveal anything new about the meaning of the listemes they examine. The question Allan poses is the following: How does the cognitive model speakers have internalized about "tomato" (a vegetable and fruit) contribute to the semantic frame of this listeme? And --he concludes-- prototypes does not answer this question. However, Allan fails to see how semantic/conceptual prototypes define linguistic constructions that -- in turn -- enhance lexical/semantic frames. The Berkeley school of thought, that of Construction Grammar (Charles Fillmore and Paul Kay 1993 et seq.) examine how our internalized knowledge of prototypes and their related categories and subcategories affects our lexical/semantic frames for lexemes occurring in constructions of real-time discourse. For instance, in account of polysemy A. Goldberg points that "lexical items are typically associated with a set of related meanings rather than a single abstract sense" (1995:44) essentially decentralizing the cognitive process of composing and decomposing semantic frames via a parallel process of discovering the radial, experiential rather than abstract related categories. Allan in his effort to balance cognitive and formalistic approaches to semantics appears to have missed out in this turn of cognitive linguistics. To remedy the perceived inadequacy of prototype theory, Allan introduces Putnam's theory of gestalt, or mental stereotype (Putnam 1979). A stereotype is a mental image of a listeme that includes the attributes of its exemplar/prototype (or "typical denotatum" in Allan's own idiolect). In this image we often are called to reconcile lexical/semantic incongruities, in semantically anomalous expressions like e.g. "blue tomato". Instead of seeking to categorize the referent (which prototype semantics does), gestalt theory would attempt to resolve the perceive incongruity in the expression. In spite of what Allan believes, Putnam's theory does not necessarily negate or compete prototype theory. In fact, it presupposes the existence of prototypical categorization with a focus on the semantic incongruities often allowed in natural language. Just because "red tomatoes" are typical, we can't deny the potential existence of "blue tomatoes". Gestalts are being perceived by means of a mechanism for individual member subcategorization, although it is undoubtedly true that the whole lies beyond the sum of its parts. The lens of perception and experience and previous learning may give a gestalt different colors. Natural language semantics should deal with what is meaningful to humans, the dynamic semantic network that resonates with their perceptions, cognition, learning and experiences, instead of accounting for an abstract, hypothetical, and non- experiential gestalt.
In Chapter 11 mood is explored "as primary illocution", and along with it tense and modals and thematic roles are analysed. Mood may indicate six primary illocutions in English (and most other languages): declarative, expressive, imperative, interrogative, interrogative subjunctive and subjunctive. Tense locates situations in time with regard to a deictic center. Grammatical aspect "captures some aspect of the development of an event." Modals are also analyzed in their root, epistemic and deontic meanings. Thematic roles are carried out by the arguments of predicates and they depend on the roles the corresponding event participants play in real discourse. Allan emphasizes the fact that thematic roles are theory- dependent, and he goes on to identify the roles of the effector (includes agent), the force, the instrument, the experiencer, the locative (includes recipient), the theme and the patient. The internal structure of effectors is hierarchical, and Allan claims the same for other roles. As a closing topic, Allan revisits GB's theta-criterion, critically reminding that Chomsky based that on an earlier criterion in Fillmore's case grammar, 1968). The theta-criterion states that there is one thematic role per clause and no NP can hold more than one thematic roles. Allan argues that verbs like give-take and sell-buy allow their goals and sources to also be agents, and that symmetric predicates and resumptive pronouns also show that there can be more instances of a thematic role in one clause. Because of the fuzziness in the definition of theta- roles, Allan suggests the sole use of two "macroroles", that of the "actor" and that of the "undergoer" in the grammar.
Chapter 12 focuses on clause predicates, a chance for the author to present Jackendoff's "lexical conceptual structures" (1995, 1997) and Role and Reference Grammar's logical predicate structures (Van Valin 1993). The latter seems to be presented more extensively than the former. The main difference between these two theories from Allan's perspective lies in the issue of whether syntax is autonomous or not. In Jackendoff's theory syntax is autonomous and semantics needs to integrate with a rather dominant syntactic theory, whereas in Van Valin's theory syntax is understood "with reference to its semantic and communicative functions." However, Jackendoff's system includes conceptual structures that Van Valin seems to ignore. Allan feels the need to compare these two theories with Wierzbicka's Natural Semantic Metalanguage (1980) discussed in earlier chapters, and make it clear that Wierzbicka's theory was purely lexicographical and does not seek to integrate with a syntactic theory. The metalanguages Van Valin and Jackendoff use are --for Allan-- ingenious in that they bridge the gap between natural language use and "a formal language such as predicate calculus and intensional logic". Van Valin's logical structures and Jackendoff's lexical conceptual structures are criticized as more economical and precise metalanguages than Wierzbicka's. Jackendoff's system is pretty comprehensive. It draws from the generative schema of I-language and adds to it a particular component, that of conceptual structure, that integrate with syntax and phonology. Conceptual structure includes linguistic, sensory and motor information for mental representation. Nouns are regarded as semantic primitives, but verbs are decomposed into function- arguments structures, as in predicate logic. Argument fusion is the combinatorial process of combining the semantic content of separate lexemes/constituents in a phrase marker (by A-marking arguments). Argument linking is a tranferring process of attaching A-marked constituents in the lexical conceptual structure to appropriate nodes in the phrase marker consistent with thematic and syntactic hierarchies. Theta- roles are assigned to arguments via argument binding. Actor- patient thematic relations are separated from motion and location. In Role and Reference Grammar predicates are classified into activities, states, achievements, accomplishments, and causatives. Some discussion on the distinctive features of the above classes are discussed as well as the fuzziness in the distinction between achievements and accomplishments. In Van Valin's system, theta roles have been summed up to the macroroles of actor (roughly, logical subject) and undergoer (roughly, logical object). Each of the macroroles hierarchically correspond to thematic roles. More in depth analyses are offered for ditransitive verbs (which are postulated as having two logical structures), copular sentences and possessive constructions. The notion of decomposition is revisited in light of the discussion on metalanguages. Allan's persistence with the notion of semantic decomposition is indicative of the importance he allocates to metalanguage and the epistemology of semantic representation via formal, formalistic and natural language methods.
Chapter 13 is devoted to English quantifiers and the semantics of NP. Although it is just preliminary to the topic, it goes a long way into analyzing "countability" in English language, compositional quantification, relationships among quantifiers and the semantics and pragmatics of simple sentences with demonstratives, and other identity statements. Some crosslinguistic observations on quantifiers are also included in the analysis. Definite and indefinite articles are presented as having other primary functions than quantification. Quantifiers in different (but successive) propositions may entail each other (monotonicity) and Allan notes that usually quantifiers demonstrate predicate rather than NP monotonicity (scope and compositionality of quantifiers were also examined). A typical NP monotonic quantifier is "all". Definite article "the" is a universal quantifier. The chapter closes with an exhaustive analysis of a simple sentence that draws on theories, terminology, tools and ideas presented throughout the book. In the Epilogue of the book, Allan goes as far as answering the question regarding the psychological reality of the semantics of quantification.
OVERALL CRITICAL EVALUATION Individual chapters have been commented on in the turn in which they were presented above. As a general observation, a big asset of Allan's book on natural language semantics from this reviewer's point of view is the multitheoretical perspective about natural language, the wealth of evidence and argumentation from different (sometimes even contradictory) theories while focusing on a particular topic, and the always present informative "notes on further reading" for the curious reader. This homo-universalis approach of Allan's exploration of semantics causes only a minor issue for the more demanding reader: certain topics are worth a deeper presentation, analysis and argumentation that a multitheoretical textbook simply does not have enough space to allow for. This book won't let you go "out there" without a good overall grasp of the field, although the beginner might be left with a bulk of often critical information to absorb.
BIBLIOGRAPHY Chaffin, Roger (1992) The concept of a semantic relation, In Frames, Fields, and Contrasts, Lehrer and Kittay (eds.), Hillsdale: Erlbaum, pp. 253-88.
Fillmore, Charles J., and Paul Kay (1993) Construction Grammar, Unpublished manuscript, University of California, Berkeley.
Goldberg, Adele E. (1995) Constructions: A Construction Grammar Approach to Argument Structure, Chicago: Chicago University Press.
Harris, Zellig S. (1951) Methods in Structural Linguistics, Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Jackendoff, Ray (1995) The boundaries of the lexicon, In Idioms: Structural and Psychological Perspectives, M. Everaert, Erik-Jan van der Linden, A. Schenk, and R. Schreuder (eds.), Hillsdale: Erlbaum, pp. 133-65.
Jackendoff, Ray (1997) Architecture of the Language Faculty, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Joos, Martin (1961) The Five Clocks, New York: Harcourt, Brace and World.
Katz, Jerrold (1972) Semantic Theory, New York: Harper and Row.
Lyons, John (1997) Semantics, 2 Vols, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
MacLaury, Robert (1997) Color and Cognition in Mesoamerica: Constructing Categories as Vantages, Austin: University of Texas Press.
Pustejovsky, James (1995) The Generative Lexicon, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Putnam, Hilary (1979) 2nd ed., Mind, Language and Reality, Philosophical Papers, 2 Vols., Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Rosch, Eleanor (1978) Principles of Categorization, In Cognition and Categorization, Eleanor Rosch and L.L.Lloyd (eds.), Hillsdale: Erlbaum, pp. 27-48.
Van Valin, Robert D. Jr. ed. (1993) Advances in Role and Reference Grammar, Amsterdam: John Benjamins.
Weinreich, Uriel (1966) Explorations in Semantic Theory, In Current Trends in Linguistics 3, Thomas A. Sebeok (ed.), The Hague: Mouton, pp. 395-477.
Wierzbicka, Anna (1980) Lingua Mentalis: the Semantics of Natural Language, Sydney: Academic Press.
Wilkins, John (1668) Essay toward a Real Character and a Philosophical Language, London: Royal Society, Fascimile, 1968, Menston: Scholar Press.
ABOUT THE REVIEWER Eleni Koutsomitopoulou is currently completing her PhD in Computational Linguistics at Georgetown University (Washington D.C.) Her research interests include natural language processing, knowledge acquisition and engineering, cognitive semantics, metaphor and conceptual modeling with neural nets especially designed for natural language. Her dissertation project is a simulation of a biologically-inspired neural network system for conceptual modeling of basic natural language constructs. She is a research analyst at LexisNexis (Dayton, OH).
|