Review: |
Date: Sun, 19 Jun 2005 21:54:24 +0300 From: Kleanthes Grohmann Subject: Chomsky's Minimalism
AUTHOR: Seuren, Pieter A. M. TITLE: Chomsky's Minimalism PUBLISHER: Oxford University Press YEAR: 2004
Kleanthes K. Grohmann, University of Cyprus
_Chomsky's Minimalism_ is an ingenuous title for a book that will undoubtedly polarize readers: It is aimed to be a substantial critique of the theoretical-conceptual foundations and scientific methodology underlying the Minimalist Program (in particular, and I will address this point below, Chomsky 1995) and its methodological and empirical shortcomings.
However, since the contents bear little resemblance to what one MIGHT expect, it is also an unfortunate title. Take _Chomsky's Universal Grammar_ (Cook & Newson 1996), for example, which is the main title of an introductory textbook to the kind of "Chomskyan linguistics" Pieter A. M. Seuren has been criticizing for quite some time (see e.g. Seuren 1996, 1998, 2001 for book-length treatments that express his 'anti-Chomskyan' stance at varying length). By analogy, an innocent reader, a novice linguist, or a casual catalogue browser might assume that he or she would be dealing with a book that goes one step beyond Cook & Newson's introduction to the Government-and-Binding Theory (GB), the best approach to the Principles-and-Parameters Theory (P&P) that formalizes a specific implementation of Universal Grammar (UG), and introduces to the reader the most current version of the generative endeavor -- the one that has become known as the Minimalist Program or minimalism. Perhaps a sub-title like 'Not an introduction', "once jokingly proposed" by the author (Pieter Seuren, personal communication), would have been a good idea after all.
This said, if one knows (of) the author, one can be pretty sure what to expect, so matters might be simple after all. (This includes, by the way, the eloquent style of writing: even if one doesn't agree with what Seuren says, how he says it is a true pleasure to read -- something I am unfortunately unable to reflect or reciprocate in this review.)
STRUCTURE
It becomes clear very early on that this book is not an introduction to minimalism -- nor is it a (favorable or critical) explanatory commentary on it. It is in fact a highly provocative and rhetorically loaded negative critique. One only needs to consult the back cover with Geoffrey Pullum's praise of this book as a "comprehensive and incisive critique of the most influential confidence trick in the history of modern linguistics." Or take the publisher's / author's synopsis of the contents as criticism of a research program that "fails to satisfy the basic criteria for sound scientific work" and manifests "the cult surrounding Chomsky and Minimalism more generally."
Let me stay with the book's exteriors for one more paragraph. If there is something I am certainly not, it's art historian or critic. But I was fascinated by the cover art ("Landscape with mountain chapel" by the Dutch surrealist painter Albert Carel Willink) and the imagery it provoked in me. So I asked my wife, who is no art historian either (and not even a linguist), to see what kind of impression it evoked in her. The response was very interesting and probably something Seuren could have had in mind himself. Her initial reaction was "It's go-go-go -- and then what?" (presumably commenting on the steps that lead into the chapel with no end point and the cave opening higher up the mountain). She felt that the painting itself expressed something very old and something very modern at the same time. But she also observed that something was missing and it wasn't quite clear what. So, from the selling point of view, this book seems to deliver a clear message.
In this review I want to show that such imagery reflects minimalism to a certain point, but that one doesn't need to take this as a negative reflection of the research program. Rather, as has been stressed over and over again by Noam Chomsky himself alongside a large number of linguists (see Hornstein, Nunes & Grohmann, in press, for a clear presentation along these lines), minimalism is a research program that follows its P&P- predecessor in many ways, but tries to minimize the humungous apparatus GB required. (Incidentally, this includes minimization of levels of representation and of internal modules, both vehemently criticized by Seuren, but perhaps not for the most convincing reasons or even in a relevant manner, as pointed out below.) Moreover, and this is the exciting part of the project, it opens up new questions about the nature of language and an adequate description thereof.
So, to pick up on the imagery of the cover, "it's go-go-go" since minimalism offers many new research areas, and at the same time there is no end in sight (yet!). This is not bad at all: All it says is that linguists can now ask interesting new questions, explore them in their glorious detail -- and develop the program in such a way that it becomes a theory of language one day. This theory will undoubtedly look VERY different from today's Minimalist Program. In fact, the Minimalist Program has undergone tremendous change already (something completely ignored by Seuren, as also pointed out below). There is no 'minimalist theory' yet, but some of us are working on it. And while contributions by Pieter Seuren and the like (e.g. Rudolf Botha, Paul Postal, or Geoffrey Pullum, all frequently quoted in this book, often from "personal communication") can be much appreciated if they are substantial and constructive, negative rhetoric and continued grief with the demise of generative semantics (and here a plethora of like-minded authors could be listed) have little room for sympathy and don't contribute to advanced understanding of the issues. For a critical perspective, one might want to consult something like Shalom Lappin and David Johnson's work (Lappin & Johnson 1997, 1999) that presents the concepts and workings of minimalism as intended and offers a critique of specific issues rather than with the present text and related ones. (Unfortunately, the latter category also includes ill-guided debates, in my opinion, such as the one initiated by the two aforementioned scholars and Robert Levine in Natural Language & Linguistic Theory a few years ago.)
For purposes of this review, each chapter will be presented in a concise paragraph including the sections contained in it (minus the 'Conclusion' sections of chapters 2 to 8), followed by some of the thoughts it stirred in me. Length considerations led me to dwell on some chapters more than on others -- for perhaps obvious reasons, I chose to concentrate on chapters 1, 2, and 8. There is much more to say, of course, and someone else would surely focus on different issues; what follows is what I focus on for lack of a different perspective.
The following outline is intended to help the reader assign title, length, and topic to each chapter discussed below:
The preface (pp. v-vi) sets the stage: for those who are not familiar with Seuren, this book is written by someone who has given up following the direction of linguistic theorizing Chomsky has developed since the 'generative semantics era' of the early 1970s, and this background is reflected on virtually every page of the book. 1 -- Chapter 1 is a comprehensive 'Introduction' (pp. 3-30) to this book in which Seuren lays out why he does what he does. 2 -- 'The Mechanism of the MP under Scrutiny' (pp. 31-50) forms chapter 2, Seuren's idiosyncratic presentation of the theoretical-conceptual foundation of minimalism. 3 -- Chapter 3 deals with 'The Language Faculty' (pp. 51-96), and Seuren lays out what Chomsky(ans) take(s) it to be, why that is misguided, and how one should really think of it. 4 -- Chapter 4 offers 'Questions of Method and Adequacy' (pp. 97-124) -- yes, it tells the reader that Chomsky's methods are unsound and don't meet scientific adequacy. 5 -- 'What Is Functional about the MP?' (pp. 125-149) is asked in chapter 5 and answered in the negative, with particular emphasis given to (perfect) language design. 6 -- 'What Is Conceptually Necessary about the MP?' (pp. 125-149) is asked in chapter 6 and answered equally in the negative, where the two main building blocks are the architecture assumed in minimalism and the motivation of the "displacement property" (i.e. what has become known analytically as 'movement'). 7 -- Chapter 7 addresses 'Surface-Driven Elements of Semantic Interpretation' (pp. 169-190) and Seuren's arguments against minimalism's abolishment of a concept like "surface structure" on the grounds of interplay with interpretation. 8 -- The concluding chapter 8 aims to disclose 'The Embarrassment of Evidence' (pp. 191-230), which turns out to be an embarrassing discussion of syntactic analysis. The book is rounded off with the references (pp. 231-238) and an index (pp. 239-244) containing authors, languages, and terms.
DISCUSSION
CHAPTER 1 opens with the 'Stated aim': "to show that Noam Chomsky's latest version of his linguistic theory, recently published as _The Minimalist Program_ (MP) (1995), though presented as the crowning achievement of the Chomskyan version of generative grammar, is in fact the clearest possible demonstration that that version is fundamentally flawed" (p. 1). Do we really need to say more? The rhetorical style of the book connects to this opening sentence seamlessly. The remaining sections of this introductory chapter are 'The hard truth about the MP', 'Further misgivings', 'Presentation and terminology', 'Mysterious paradigm mixing', and 'Empirical issues'. Here Seuren paves the way for his extensive discussion and critique of the methodology behind Chomsky's minimalism (as opposed to an 'alternative minimalism', for example).
As Seuren states in the Preface, he understands that "the focus of attention [in minimalism] has shifted from theorizing about grammar writing to the loftier level of methodological reflection" (v). Consequently, he spends considerable time dissecting issues of contention with such a "loftier level" throughout the book, introduced in CHAPTER 1. He does so in particular in the chapters I will not discuss in any depth below.
My reasons for this decision are simple. By concentrating on Seuren's -- often misguided or misinformed -- portrayal of minimalist concepts and analysis as well as his strong rhetoric, I believe I can highlight much better what goes wrong in the book. Recall that by virtue of its title, one can reasonably assume this book to be a critique of minimalism as a whole. At least I do so and in the absence of an alternative review, stick to it. If Seuren's main goal was to denounce the methodology behind Chomsky's minimalist approach, he could have indicated this in the title or pursued it more consequently by not attempting to discuss the theoretical apparatus. Since half the chapters deal with technical issues in one way or another, and since there are limitations of space, I believe my decision is well justified.
To return to CHAPTER 1, part of the "hard truth" argument is that "in the wider circles of intellectuals" (i.e. outside linguistics), "there is a widespread belief that Chomskyan linguistics is the only serious form of scientific syntax" (p. 7). And footnote 1 on this page, as sprinkled throughout the book, picks out a random example which Seuren comments with the words that "[o]ne could cite numerous other authors who put blind faith in Chomsky's linguistics without, apparently, having actually studied his works." I'm sure many readers will agree that a 'Chomskyan linguist' would jump up and exclaim, "I wish!" -- the impact on non- linguistic (biological, psychological, or any other) realms of science "Chomskyan linguistics" has had over the past 50 years is by far not as deeply-rooted as Seuren and other critics like to make it sound (and even in linguistics, generativists don't constitute the majority if we look at numbers world-wide). I don't see too many core "Chomskyan linguistics" courses taught in psychology or biology departments, not even an exegesis of the most fundamental concepts generative grammar has developed in the past five decades. And most 'current' references to generative grammar provided by non-generativists and non-linguists usually stop in 1965, or the early 1970s at best.
In addition, Seuren is guilty of his own accusations. Most relevant for the present review is the fact that Seuren sets out to criticize "Chomsky's minimalism" (as the title promises), but in reality the book is just, in Seuren's words, a critique of Chomsky's "_The Minimalist Program_ (MP) (1995):" to refer to this as the "latest version of his linguistic theory" (p. 3) and the 'definitive minimalism' (my term) some 10 years after publication indicates that Seuren criticizes an entire approach "without, apparently, having actually studied his works." As any recently trained student of "Chomskyan linguistics" is aware, MP has been followed up by a number of papers in which Chomsky clarifies, modifies, and extends the program laid out in 1995, in particular Chomsky (2000b, 2001, 2004, 2005) of which the first three should have been available to Seuren before the final draft of his book. Since he cites work dated 2003, a 2001 manuscript published as Chomsky (2004) could have been accessed -- and studied -- easily. Moreover, _The Minimalist Program_ -- to repeat, a first sketch of a new direction in research -- contains four chapters, two of which are commonly taken to be precursors to minimalism, not minimalist contributions in and of themselves (chapters 1 and 2, which appeared as Chomsky & Lasnik 1993 and Chomsky 1991, respectively).
CHAPTER 2 tries to present 'Some "guiding ideas"' of MP and offers 'A closer inspection of the "computational system"' (in particular, the operations Select, Merge, and Move as well as the concepts Reference Set and Numeration).
Apart from the fact that no post-1995 reference of Chomsky's (or anyone else's!) work on theoretical issues in a minimalist setting has been consulted, giving this chapter (and the entire book) a rather outdated feel, Seuren does not seem to have understood the mechanics presented in MP all that well. (And no, I do not consider the works he does mention, Chomsky (1998, 2000a, 2002), relevant in this respect; neither do I accept the author's stated aim, reiterated in personal communication, to look at "the loftier level of methodological reflection" as a valid reason -- as mentioned above, Seuren could have just abstained from an inclusion of the technicalities altogether.) This begins on a trivial level with the continued use of the term "human language computational system" (which Chomsky calls CHL for "computational system of human language") inside double quotes, suggesting either a quotation of Chomsky's use (in which case it's mistaken) or an apprehension towards the term (in which case it's not clear why he doesn't stick to Chomsky's term).
But there are also some technical problems in Seuren's presentation. When he claims, for example, that "[n]o argument is offered for the implicit assumption ([Chomsky] 1995: 243 and elsewhere) that branchings resulting from Merge should be binary" (p. 34), the reader might get the impression that this is a novelty within syntactic theorizing proposed first within minimalism. Binary branching has been a standard assumption in P&P- approaches, or "Chomskyan linguistics," since at least Kayne (1984) -- a source cited and discussed as early as chapter 1 of _The Minimalist Program_ (Chomsky 1995: 61-62). Binary branching itself thus need not be re-introduced and -justified; the existing literature is large enough and those readers of MP that are interested in it, will be familiar with the relevant literature or at least willing to read up on it. If Seuren's point is that binarity necessarily holding of the technical operation Merge is not clearly enough argued for, he may want to read Chomsky's justification for a bare phrase structure approach again and familiarize himself with Chomsky's adoption of set theoretic argumentation. If this is not formal enough either, or simply wrong in Seuren's opinion, he may say so and offer his arguments. For clearer presentation, he may also (read and) refer to the first two papers on phases (Chomsky 2000, 2001, circulated in manuscript form in 1998 and 1999, respectively), in which Chomsky sheds enough light on the issue to either fully understand the why or to reject the approach altogether -- but this can be reviewed or criticized in better ways than Seuren's off-hand remark provides.
The same goes for Seuren's discussion of labels. The question what serves as the new constituent label when A and B are merged, the MP answer is either A or B: {G, {A, B}} with G = A or G = B. Seuren considers an option that was not entertained by Chomsky (who did offer two alternative conclusions -- intersection and union of A and B, respectively -- and rejecting both, as correctly reported by Seuren): the new label is neither A nor B, "an option grammar cannot do without" (p. 35). Even if we leave endocentricity issues aside, a hallmark concept in linguistic theorizing predating both "Chomskyan linguistics" and minimalism (cf. Harris 1951: 275-276, Lyons 1968: 231-235), Seuren's option is still not compatible with the Inclusiveness Condition (Chomsky 1995: 228) -- applied to minimalism, I refer the interested reader in particular to sections 2.4 and 6.2 of Hornstein, Nunes & Grohmann (in press). Likewise, even if one agrees with Seuren's claim just quoted, a formulation in terms of "proposition" or "predicate" as he does (see also his sections 3.5.1 and 6.2.1) doesn't seem fruitful in light of independent minimalist assumptions. Among other things, these concepts are not primitives of the theory. In any case, a slightly more detailed discussion beyond the three paragraphs offered might have been useful to determine whether Chomsky's (and all his 'followers'') choice was justified, partially correct, or totally wrong.
Seuren also criticizes the other important operation first clearly formulated in minimalism, Select (which takes a lexical item from the Numeration and enters it into the syntactic computation, the derivation). He wants to cast doubt on its purported being "conceptually necessary" with the help of Paul Postal's observation ("personal communication") that a sentence such as 'The French word for milk is 'lait'' could never be generated: "In the Select-and-Merge setup, sentences containing such ad hoc words could never be generated, since such words are not in the English lexicon. The entire Select-and-Merge system thus seems ill- conceived" (p. 34). The 'argumentation' makes me wonder. Does this particular type of case -- which involves much more than a sketch of a minimalist approach to linguistic theory can reasonably set out to accomplish (presumably, issues of interlanguage, multi-lingual lexicons, and so on) -- now render the entire system "ill-conceived"? I leave the judgment to the reader. (One could also mention in this context, as Winnie Lechner points out to me, that metalinguistic reference is possible to everything that can be written, not only to parts of the lexicon unique to a particular language. In other words, there must be a function which takes as input everything that can be expressed in writing and imports it into the lexicon.)
Other lamentations of Seuren's include the complaint that "on p. 155 [of Chomsky 1995 -- note to the reader: this is the pre-minimalist chapter 2] it is suggested that existential 'there' should be considered 'an LF- affix', a kind of element not mentioned before" (p. 38). One might point out that GB enjoyed a very similar analysis of anaphors (cf. Lebeaux 1983, Chomsky 1986), so this concept is anything but new. Later on in the book, Seuren attacks the analysis of expletive 'there' (and existential constructions in general) within "Chomskyan linguistics" further. One may not share Chomsky's insistence on constantly overhauled analyses of 'there', but one surely has to admire the consequence with which theoretical advancements are followed through and applied to this construction, which has gained notoriety for exactly this reason. None of the elegance and technical finesse managed to secure Seuren's appreciation -- or reflection in the book.
This chapter contains a large number of bones I have to pick, most of which I cannot discuss here for length considerations. Regarding the Reference Set, for example, Seuren may be pleased to learn that this concept seems to have been given up around 1997 (see some papers collected in Wilder, Gärtner & Bierwisch 1997 for discussion). Likewise, the Numeration has evolved into the (Lexical) Array since Chomsky (2000) -- whether his original 'doubts' (if one can characterize thus his loose musings) disappear, however, is a different question. Other issues of contention include Seuren's derivational tree diagram (Figure 2.1 on p. 38, adapted from Johnson & Lappin 1997: 282) and the ensuing discussion which highlights gaps in his technical understanding of the core minimalist concepts (Select, Merge, Move, and Spell-Out).
On a more philosophical level, Seuren addresses some interesting issues that "Chomskyan linguistics" faces quite independently of 'minimalism' (such as questions about evolution and exaptation of language, language acquisition as instantaneous development, or the cognitive/grammatical distinction, for example). Here one may choose to agree or disagree with Seuren -- but the style of presentation does unfortunately not invite readers like myself to take the content all that seriously.
CHAPTER 3 contains five main sections: 'Principles and Parameters: a historical note', 'Modularity and the random-generator position', 'Chomsky's ambiguous realism', 'Instantaneous language evolution', and 'An alternative view of the language faculty'.
One of the most interesting aspects of this chapter is Seuren's criticism of the architectural reduction of levels of interpretation. Where MP tries to reduce the four GB levels by eliminating D- and S-structure (leaving just Logical Form and Phonetic Form), Seuren argues that there should in fact be four interface levels: (i) "[t]he output end of the thought- producing machinery," (ii) "[t]he output end of the lexicon," (iii) "[t]he output end of the grammar module," and (iv) "[t]he output end of the phonetic-orthographic machinery." However, since the chapter is, as all others, phrased in such an attacking manner on Chomsky(an linguistics), it is hard to see how, if at all, Seuren's sound architectural ideas could be made fit into a minimalist model -- or even in how far, if at all, these offer a challenge.
CHAPTER 4 is a provocative discussion of or attack on 'What can confirm or disconfirm a paradigm?', 'Chomsky as a higher authority', 'Ecologism and formalism', and 'What to do with evidence?'.
CHAPTER 5 attacks the 'The minimalist version of functionalism' and asks 'How perfect is language?'. The section heading 'Optimal language design and model building: the "fable"' speaks for itself. Seuren then addresses 'Language and communication' and attempts to show in which ways 'The minimalist program is not minimalist'. 'Why choices? The case of Mauritian Creole' is followed by 'Sociolinguistic factors' that should be taken into account.
CHAPTER 6 is an attempt to justify an answer in the negative to two questions: 'Conceptual motivation for the random generator?' and 'Is the "displacement property" conceptually motivated?'.
CHAPTER 7 is mostly empirical. Once 'The question stated' is on the table, Seuren goes on to attack analytical shortcomings of "Chomsky's Minimalism" by considering 'Focusing strategies', 'Presuppositions', and 'Operator scope'.
The section headings describe the content of CHAPTERS 4 to 7 very well. In fact, one might be tempted to take these chapters, "the loftier level of methodological reflection" proper, to be the core of the book. If that is so, my decision to concentrate on the other three chapters (plus CHAPTER 8 addressed below) may not have been the wisest. However, the chapters I do discuss offer most for the direction pursued in this review -- and they address issues I happen to understand best and know more about. As a consequence, I was able to point to a number of misunderstandings and - interpretations on Seuren's side regarding the technical implementations and the real conceptual aims of MP. To lay out the methodology underlying minimalism that Seuren takes issue with might deserve a separate review -- it simply cannot be integrated into the present one which concentrates on exposing and clarifying Seuren (mis)presentation of MP in other areas.
The chapters I am skipping over ever so gently contain mostly well-known quibbles with "Chomskyan linguistics" -- these are neither specific to minimalism nor new in any way, but in fact go back to the early 1970s, when scholars like Seuren got upset with the post-Aspects model and the 'generative semantics war' (which in and of itself is arguably not the best way to put it, but since I wasn't around at the time, who am I to talk?). And unfortunately, the reader finds a lot of Chomsky-bashing (as becomes clear from the section headings). Other, perhaps less known, quibbles concern Seuren's interpretation of the history of science, with particular reference to the figures mentioned most prominently by Chomsky himself (Galileo and Descartes, but also Copernicus, Newton, and Darwin) and the relevance of Cartesian investigation to linguistic methodology.
They also contain some data discussion (continued in the final chapter 8) in which Seuren wants to dismantle any viability of minimalist analysis on the basis of a few facts about language. These include prepositional adjuncts (section 4.1.1) and operator scope (section 7.4). I pick out these two issues for the simple reason that Seuren uses them 'best' to show how inadequate minimalism is, and because he cross-references both sections, in particular the idiosyncratic take he adopts on these two constructions. In section 4.1.1, Seuren offers an incomprehensible nine- page treatment of prepositional adjuncts within his own framework, "semantic syntax" (Seuren 1996), while, at the same time, leaving the reader in the dark as to why prepositional adjuncts would constitute such disastrous empirical counter-evidence to a minimalist approach. (And even if one contends with Seuren, reinforced in personal communication, that he "do[es] not pick out [these constructions] to show the inadequacy of the MP but to show the superior adequacy of [his] Semantic Syntax," one wonders why he chose to include them in a book that is apparently mainly concerned with "the loftier level of methodological reflection.")
The three-page discussion of operator scope -- and in particular, the fact that scoping elements must be present at LF ("in the logico-semantic analysis") -- highlights Seuren's motives once again: "[t]his point is implicitly recognized in May (1977), where the rule schema of Operator Lowering, developed in the framework of generative semantics, is simply reversed into Operator Raising (but without attribution)" (188). (In note 1 on p. 171, Seuren attributes these discoveries to Lakoff (1971) and McCawley (1972).) He continues noting with interest that "the determination of operator scope is not mentioned in Chomsky's later writings." Somewhat flippantly but with reference to Seuren's own words, I would like to respond, "Come on, read "Chomsky's later writings" for a change!"
CHAPTER 8 is a continuation of the analytical shortcomings addressed in the previous chapter. Here Seuren investigates in some more detail 'Deletion and Raising in infinitival complements', various 'Copying phenomena', and the infamous 'Existential 'there''.
It starts very nicely with a footnote in which Seuren challenges minimalists (or so one could understand this note) that "the burden of proof lies with those who wish to deny surface structure as a level of representation, not with us" (192). Au contraire (whether or not this is in the lexicon of an English speaker), the burden of proof lies with those who wish to continue believing in S(urface)-structure as a level of representation! At least, so one must argue in criticizing minimalism in its own right, as a continuation of the successful P&P-approach of GB with its stated aims. In GB, S-structure was solely motivated theory- internally, as Chomsky (1995: chap. 2) recaps (for a concise discussion, see e.g. chapter 2 of Hornstein, Nunes & Grohmann, in press). If Seuren means his own (or other continuations from the generative semantics era or the Aspects-model) understanding of S-structure, call it "surface structure," then we can't easily come to a decision -- nor can we easily compare the two. GB S-structure and Seuren's "surface structure" simply have different formal properties and hence a different standing in the respective approaches. Pitting these two notions against one another absolves anyone from providing a "burden of proof" -- at this point, without further discussion (on a technical level, which Seuren does not provide), it's comparing apples and pears.
A lot more can be said on the 'disastrous' empirical evidence against MP that Seuren offers (see section headings), where he ignores minimalist work on raising and inflected infinitives in Portuguese, exceptional Case- marking/subject-to-object raising in Balkan subjunctives, purported bans on rightward movement, and so on. Or even the claim that, since "[c]opying is a widespread phenomenon in the languages of the world," "it finds no place at all in the MP" (216). Once again, Seuren's corpus of material under discussion (which is basically limited to Chomsky 1995), a book of 420 pages (including references and index) simply cannot provide the motivation behind minimalism, the conceptualization of the program, the technical basics, and an exhaustive analysis of all facts found in human language(s). This is why _The Minimalist Program_ is a comprehensive presentation of a minimalist approach to linguistic theory which can be extended, adopted, and amended to find a satisfactory treatment of all this -- collectively, by all linguists interested. And this is indeed what some of us are working towards.
I'd rather close with rebutting an(other) utterly unnecessary ad hominem attack Seuren couldn't hold back. In the context of 'believe' vs. 'expect', Seuren fights with an answer to the question why the first is only an ECM verb, while the second can also be a control verb. He can't find one and comments his frustration: "No answer is provided. One fears that the author is simply forgetful, or careless" (205). This is followed by a wonderful footnote, which I quote in its totality:
"Some carelessness is apparent anyway on the same p. 345 [of Chomsky (1995)], where, in the same context, the sentence (172b) 'I expect someone to leave early' is discussed. Five lines below the example presented, one reads: "In the ECM structure (172b), H [the relevant Case-assigning head] assigns no case, so 'John' raises to the checking domain of Agro [Agreement for object] in the matrix clause." A little care would have shown the author that, for once, the sentence isn't about 'John', but about 'someone'." (205: fn. 8)
At this point one wants to jump up and... On a more peaceful note, I cannot help but state that Seuren is just as "forgetful" or "careless" as he accuses Chomsky of being. Some such instances are:
- in section 2.2.1 on p. 34, one reads: "see section 2.2.1." - the German for 'president' in sentence (29a) on p. 221 is misspelled - on p. 188, a section "4.1.1.1" is referred to, which doesn't exist (intended was one 4.1.1 less)
CONCLUSION
Do I have anything positive to say about Seuren's book? No, not really. Since it's rhetorically very hostile, it can hardly be called "balanced" and since it doesn't refer to any real literature or research, it can hardly be called "informed." These factors lead to only one conclusion: _Chomsky's Minimalism_ is just not informing.
Is it at least entertaining? If you like Chomsky-bashing, sure thing! (Then you'll surely find a warm welcome at all those websites and blogs dedicated to this type of activity and references to _The Anti-Chomsky Reader_ and other works -- one of which, Michael Covington's (at ), praises the book under review with the words: "It is all the more impressive if you've met Seuren (as I have) and realize that he is a very mild-mannered person." Well, big deal. I haven't met Seuren and I'm sorry, but I can't say that this is the style of "a very mild-mannered person.")
Does it provide new insights into the study and/or architecture of grammar, analysis, minimalism, and so on? My answer is a very simple "No."
I conclude that this book offers very little beyond heavy rhetoric and misunderstandings-turned-unjustified-criticism. Admittedly, this review was written by someone who is very biased against the kind of criticisms the author offers. That said, the author himself is very biased towards the program he set out to criticize. To get a different impression of the book and its virtues and possible shortcomings (or as I would put it, its shortcomings and possible virtues), one would need to read a review by someone as antagonistic to the Minimalist Program as Seuren, or someone who went "with Chomsky" a long way and split for whatever reason with the rise of the Minimalist Program.
REFERENCES
Chomsky, Noam (1986) Knowledge of Language: Its Nature, Origin, and Use. New York: Praeger.
Chomsky, Noam (1995) The Minimalist Program. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Chomsky, Noam (1998) Linguagem e mente: Pensamentos atuais sobre antigos problemas [= Language and Mind: Current Thoughts on Ancient Problems, Part I and Part II. Lectures presented at the Universidade de Brasilia, 1996.]. Brasilia: Editora Universidade de Brasilia. [Seuren adds: "(Page references are to the English text as sent from MIT.)"]
Chomsky, Noam (2000a) New Horizons in the Study of Language and Mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Chomsky, Noam (2000b) 'Minimalist Inquiries: The Framework'. In R. Martin, M. Davis & J. Uriagereka, eds. Step by Step: Essays on Minimalist Syntax in Honor of Howard Lasnik. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 89-155.
Chomsky, Noam (2001) 'Derivation by Phase'. In M. Kenstowicz, ed. Ken Hale: A Life in Language. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1-52.
Chomsky, Noam (2002) On Nature and Language. Ed. by A. Belletti & L. Rizzi. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Chomsky, Noam (2004) 'Beyond Explanatory Adequacy'. In A. Belletti, ed. Structures and Beyond: The Cartography of Syntactic Structures, Vol. 3. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 104-131.
Chomsky, Noam (2005) 'On Phases'. Ms., MIT.
Cook, Vivian & Mark Newson (1996) Chomsky's Universal Grammar: An Introduction. Oxford: Blackwell.
Harris, Zellig S. (1951) Methods in Structural Linguistics. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press. [NB: Page references quoted above refer to the fourth imprint of 1964 published under the title _Structural Linguistics_.]
Hornstein, Norbert, Jairo Nunes, and Kleanthes K. Grohmann (in press) Understanding Minimalism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [expected: September 2005]
Johnson, David E. & Shalom Lappin (1997) 'A Critique of the Minimalist Program'. Linguistics & Philosophy 20, 272-333.
Johnson, David E. & Shalom Lappin (1999) Local Constraints vs. Economy. Stanford, Calif.: CSLI Publications
Kayne, Richard. (1984) Connectedness and Binary Branching. Dordrecht: Foris.
Lakoff, George. (1971) 'On Generative Semantics'. In D. D. Steinberg and L. A. Jakobovits, eds. Semantics: An Interdisciplinary Reader in Philosophy, Linguistics and Psychology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 232-296.
Lebeaux, David (1983) 'A Distributional Difference between Reciprocals and Reflexives'. Linguistic Inquiry 14, 723-730.
Lyons, John (1968) Introduction to Theoretical Linguistics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
May, Robert. (1977) 'The Grammar of Quantification'. Ph.D. diss., MIT.
McCawley, James D. (1972) 'A Program for Logic'. In D. Davidson & G. Harman, eds. Semantics of Natural Language. Dordrecht: Reidel, 498-554.
Seuren, Pieter A. M. (1996) Semantic Syntax. Oxford: Blackwell.
Seuren, Pieter A. M. (1998) Western Linguistics: An Historical Introduction. Oxford: Blackwell.
Seuren, Pieter A. M. (2001) A View of Language. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Wilder, Chris, Hans-Martin Gärtner & Manfred Bierwisch, eds. (1997) The Role of Economy Principles in Linguistic Theory. Berlin: Akademie Verlag.
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
For discussion of the material reviewed and comments on this review, I am grateful to Winnie Lechner and Pieter Seuren, for encouragement and feedback, to Cedric Boeckx and Norbert Hornstein.]
|
|
ABOUT THE REVIEWER:
ABOUT THE REVIEWER The reviewer is Assistant Professor of Theoretical Linguistics in the Department of English Studies at the University of Cyprus in Nicosia. His main interests lie in syntactic theory (esp. within Principles-and- Parameters approaches) and comparative syntax (esp. Germanic, Romance, Slavic, Greek). He has worked on different topics, such as wh- constructions, left dislocation and resumption, cliticization, and reverse locality effects, ("anti-locality"). He is also a member of the expert panel of the Ask-A-Linguist service offered by LINGUIST List. For further personal and professional information see .
|
|
Versions: |
Format: |
Hardback |
ISBN: |
0195173058 |
ISBN-13: |
N/A
|
Pages: |
256 |
Prices: |
U.S. $
72.00
|
Format: |
Paperback |
ISBN: |
0195173066 |
ISBN-13: |
N/A
|
Pages: |
256 |
Prices: |
U.S. $
29.95
|
|
|
|
|